In the beginning of the previous chapter, I offered two theses that
credit-giving views of science endorse: (CG1) there is a world independent
of human inquiry, and (CG2) knowledge of that world is such by virtue of
accurately describing it. We can pick out a parallel pair of theses
for extreme social constructivist views to endorse: (SC1) our only access
to reality is through social processes, and (SC2) reality is constituted
by the social processes that allow us “access” to it. This is as
neat a comparison as I would allow myself, and complicating issues turn
up right away. Most apparently, the order is reversed in the second
pair. The epistemological claim comes first and the ontological one
second. I did this because there is a dependence relation between
the two. According to the way social constructivist arguments typically
go, we should believe (SC2) because we recognize (SC1). By way of
comparison, (CG2) is dependent on (CG1) in that we could not know an indepent
world if one did not exist. This is a simple and straightforward
dependence that causes the credit-giver no problems.
The dependence relation between (SC1) and (SC2) is, however,
a problematic one. It consists of a unjustified move from a claim
about what we know to a claim about what there is. Even if we do
not have any access at all to a reality separate from our social interests,
that does not necessarily mean that there is no reality separate from our
social interests. A move from an epistemological claim to a ontological
one is not warranted. Especially in this particular case, quite the
opposite is true. If (SC1) is true, and we take the fact that our
access to reality is unavoidably social to mean that we cannot perceive
what reality is truly like, then we can make no claim about the character
of that reality. (SC2) is a claim about the character of reality,
namely that no independent reality exists, and since we have agreed that
we can’t know about that, (SC2) cannot be consistently asserted.
A probable response from social constructivists like Latour and Woolgar
is that (SC2) is the kind of move characteristic of the idealism of the
modern period. The social constructions of scientists, as they are
all we have epistemically, are constituative of reality. This move
depends on the idea that we should build ontology on epistemology.
I suggest that it only sounds plausible given a starting point of Cartesian-demon-type
skepticism which I will not fully argue against. I offer a partial
respone (I happen to think it is good enough) in the following section,
but avoid engaging the global skeptic fully, as that would bot be within
the scope of this project.
On this idealist rendering of (SC2), it does seem to follow from
(SC1)--if we allow an unusual use of the term ‘reality.’ To me, this
use of the term is so unusual that it almost exactly reverses the accepted,
intuitivie meaning of the term, using it to apply to our social (not determined
by correspondence with states of affairs in the world) construction as
opposed to an independent world. ‘Reality’ is conventionally used
to refer to an independent world, while this use specifically picks out
something that is not an independent world. I suggest that this misuse
of ‘reality’ makes (SC1) and the idealistically rendered (SC2) entirely
counterintuitive. Latour and Woolgar would probably cheerfully agree.
But the traditional concept that reality is something “out-there,” prior
to and independent of our inquiry, should not be abandoned so quickly.
Even on the coherent--but counterintuitive--idealist rendering, we can
still ask whether (SC1) and (SC2) are true or not. I contend that
they are not. The way I propose we decide is by checking the relevant
state of affairs in the world. This may be unfair to social constructivists
like Latour and Woolgar, who say that we cannot do so and that any account
will survive or fail or be modified based on its power to convince, but
let me just say that--for me and many others--an account’s power to convince
is greatly increased by how well it matches with the state of affairs it
putatively describes.
The observable world
Ordinary, mid-size objects like tables, chairs, dogs, cats, cows, and
automobiles can be confidently described as independent of human inquiry.
Of course, our understanding of these objects is social to a certain degree.
I wouldn’t call a table a ‘table’ if I had not been brought up speaking
English, and I wouldn’t have a certain set of ideas about what a table
is used for, where it comes from, and so on if I had not been brought up
in (or exposed to) a society which uses tables in the way ours does.
In short, I might not know an object with legs and a flat, horizontal surface
as a ‘table’ or know what such an object is used for. But it is also
obvious that there are features of tables which do not depend on social
factors like language and upbringing. Being able to stub one’s toe
one a table leg comes to mind. Let me stick to the example of being
able to see the features of things like tables. The surface of a
table will reflect light which can be sensed by the human eye. This
process will tend to bring about a belief about the presence, location,
and other features of the table in the human observer. These beliefs
are caused and justified by causal interaction with the table, just as
the pain in one’s toe is caused by interaction with the table leg.
Interactions like these can be performed by anyone with the relevant sensory
apparatus, regardless of social factors. We can devise two tests
to effectively prove that beliefs formed about the table are not socially
constructed. (1) Have people from significantly different social
backgrounds interact with the table in the same way--e.g., stub their toes,
identify its location, size, color, etc. (2) Have people in the (as
close as possible) same social situation interact with many different tables
and see if their interactions differ in correspondence to the differences
in the tables--here we might use trick tables that do not feel as hard
as they look or other oddities as a check for the consistent application
of shared social schema for table-interaction. The results, we can
be sure, would indicate that much of the way people interact with tables
is not determined by social factors. We perceive consistency in the
features of ordinary objects like tables because their physical behavior
is independent of our epistemic interaction with them. By this I
mean to allow for the fact that we can, of course, interact with ordinary
objects. Stubbing one’s toe on a table leg, for instance, might jar
the table. This is a causal interaction between physical bodies and
is not the result of a social construction. But the kind of interaction
indicated by (SC1) and (SC2)--something like the idea that my socially-induced
concepts about tables are the reason that they can be moved by kicking
them--should be ruled out.
Richard Boyd puts the point nicely. He says that realists
must affirm the “no noncausal contribution thesis,” while constructivists
will deny it. The thesis is that “human social practices make no
noncausal contribution to the causal structures of the phenomena scientists
study.” Of course humans can interact causally with objects--they
can build houses, eat plants, and stub their toes--and social practices
can even be the source of causal interaction, as someone who lives in a
carpentered society like ours is more likely to build a house, thereby
interacting with the materials she uses in a certain way because of that
social factor. But social practices do not interact with the world
in a noncausal way--an example of which would be that table legs are actually
hard enough to hurt people’s toes because of socially-transmitted fears
about hurting toes focused on tables. This would be the kind of reality-constituting
social activity that Latour and Woolgar attribute to their endocrinologists.
Scientific realists must be committed to the idea that this does not happen.
That an independent, real world of ordinary objects exists is
surely the best explanation for the consistency of our perception of ordinary
objects. As I mentioned before, I do not want to get caught up in
the argument against global skepticism. I think that the strength
and cross-cultural consistency of the way we experience the observable
world is argument enough against the skeptic. To deny an independent,
real world would necessitate positing something else that performs the
same function; that is, something else that acts just like an independent
real world. There is a lack of economy to such a model and there
is, I think, intuitive inclination to say, “If it acts just like an independent,
real world, what else could it be?” Social constructivists, of course,
may be willing to say that something that walks like a duck and quacks
like a duck is still a social construction, but this means ignoring the
power of a theory committed to reality to explain the consistency of the
behavior of the observable world.
From observable to unobservable
I have mentioned that I think constructivists have a problem with the
observable world. Bloor admits that we can be right about the observable
world, but he thinks scientific theories that invoke unobservable entities
or phenomena can never be shown to be true because observable evidence
will never fully determine the correctness of any theory. This commits
him to positing a cut-off point where objects cease to be observable.
Latour and Woolgar and Knorr-Cetina either follow the same strategy or,
as I suggested before, don’t even believe that we can know about an independent,
observable world. If they follow the latter strategy, they are wrong,
as I argued in the previous section. Let us charitably assume that
all the social constructivists agree about the independence of the observable
world and so are committed to a cut-off point between observable and unobservable.
Bloor does not mention where he thinks such a cut-off might be.
He might not need to, if the idea is plausible. Is it? Grover
Maxwell has argued that there is no possible principled cut-off between
observable and unobservable entities, only a continuum of harder-and-harder
to observe. He refers to the logical empiricist’s idea that
looking through a microscope does not mean looking at physical things.
He says, “if this analysis is strictly adhered to, we cannot observe physical
things through opera glasses or even through ordinary spectacles, and one
begins to wonder about the status of what we see through an ordinary windowpane.”
Maxwell argues that there is a continuum from looking through a vacuum
to looking through reading glasses, up to looking through a high-powered
microscope. Any line drawn between observable and unobservable will
be arbitrary and depend on contextual factors like the resolution of available
microscopes. How can we justify the idea that things on one side
of our arbitrary line have physical thinghood and those on the other side
do not? If we take any two consecutive stages in the continuum, can
we really say that things observed at one stage are “slightly less real”
than those at the previous? Maxwell’s arguments are to the effect
that, given the continuity between observability and unobservability, and
the fact that a continuity between existence and non-existence sounds nonsensical,
the view that unobservables are significantly, ontologically different
in themselves from observables is implausible. His article occupies
a place within a debate between realism and logical empiricism, with its
view that unobservables are “theoretical entities,” “convenient fictions,”
or something of the kind. Maxwell argues against the theoretical/observational
dichotomy. But the realist claims he makes can be aimed at social
constructivism as well, since it includes the ideas that (at least) unobservables
do not really exist, but are constructed. Instead of the theoretical/observational
dichotomy, we have a socially constructed/observational dichotomy to fight.
Does Maxwell’s argument destroy the distinction between observables
and unobservables? Bas van Fraassen has countered Maxwell by claiming
that, although there may be a continuum, there are clear cases of unobservables
which would surely occupy a place close to the end of the continuum.
Such entities--the electron comes to mind--might still be able to take
their place in Bloor’s theory as the unobservables about which we can never
have true theories. Van Fraassen argues that the observability of
bodies seen through a telescope comes from the fact that we could, in principle,
go and look (at the moons of Jupiter, for example). We cannot,
in actuality or in principle, go and look at an electron. Quantum
uncertainty aside, a being that could see electrons would simply not be
human. There is a genuine limit to what we can observe. But
there is more to Maxwell’s continuum argument than just stating it and
exclaiming that there is no principled difference between observables and
unobservables.
The continuum argument applied to microscopy, despite the fact that
it does not prove that there are no unobservables in principle, is important
as a model or outline of the type of argument that is needed to demystify
unobservables. What is important about it is what it indicates about
the relation, in principle, between successive stages of magnification.
Take a hypothetical first stage of magnification, which will be very weak.
We can look through the microscope and see magnified bodies. But
an observer with very good vision can look closely at the bodies with the
naked eye in order to compare what she sees with the microscope image.
This is what I call an observable-to-observable check. It validates
the first stage of magnification, putting it at a similar level of reliability
with ordinary observation. We can then use the first stage to validate
a second stage, and so on.
Of course each successive stage cannot be exactly compared.
There are elements of the magnified image which are simply not available
at a previous stage, otherwise magnification would be pointless.
But we can at least see a mapping of the images on to each other that allows
comparison. If a circular body is looked at under a microscope, the
magnified image reveals a larger circular object--and of course this holds
for as great an amount of detail as can be perceived in the unmagnified
image. Ian Hacking offers another argument which lends support to
the significance of the observable-to-observable check which he calls the
argument of the grid. Tiny, numbered metal grids are used to
identify and compare the arrangement of microscopic bodies. These
grids are manufactured by drawing a large grid with numbered squares in
ink, photographically reducing it, and depositing metal on the resulting
micrograph. If we then look at the tiny grid through a microscope,
we see exactly the same grid and numbers as were drawn in the large version.
We know the microscope image is accurate because we know what the grid
ought to look like, and that is what we see.
This kind of continuum argument, based on showing the reliability
of moving successively farther and farther away from ordinary observability,
allows us to have confidence in the similarity of the microscopic world
to the observable world. It works for telescopy in a similar way.
On earth, we can look at something far away through a telescope and then
go check with the naked eye. In space, we have “gone and checked”
as far as the moon--in terms of naked-eye vision. We could, in principle,
go farther. The continuum argument in microscopy is not limited
to optical microscopes. Using something like the stage-by-stage check
I rehearsed above, we can compare the representations of something as complex
as an electron microscope with the representations of methods we have a
great deal of confidence in, like optical microscopes. At a
low resolution, electron microscopes provide images that can be compared
with those of optical microscopes, which gives us confidence in the accuracy
of this fundamentally different process.
I also think this argument of degrees of observability helps
us to infer the observability--in principle--of organisms in the past.
The physical impossibility of time travel obviously prevents a straightforward
“go and check” strategy, but the time that passes in a normal human lifetime
allows us to learn a considerable amount. We can, for example, observe
a cow easily enough. Say the animal dies and the body is left to
decompose. We then know that the resultant skeleton came from the
observed cow. The observability of an organism which lived in the
past and left a skeleton can be inferred by way of analogy with our late
cow. Fossilization happens within five to ten years, and so can be
observed by humans as well, giving us reason to believe that fossilized
skeletons of animals never seen by humans would have been as observable
as cows, had anyone been there to look. The other part of the solution
is being able to explain the process by which unobservables become observable.
Explainability lends great support to the lack of a principled difference--although
it may not sound persuasive to a social constructivist, who will doubt
the explanation as much as the observation. What is important to
my use of the continuum argument is the possibility of an observable-to-observable
check, which is what the “go and check” strategy with terrestrial telescopy
and the analogy argument for the observability-in-principle of past organisms
are.
How does the continuum argument factor in my appraisal of the
difference between observables and unobservables and what does that mean
for the reality of the unobservable world? The power of microscopes
to produce accurate images of unobservable entities in effect makes those
entities observable. The observable-to-observable check gives us
confidence in the process. The comparability of successive stages
gives us confidence in the magnitude to which we use the process.
The fact that unobservable entities under magnification behave like observables
viewed with the naked eye combined with the very idea of a continuum of
degrees of observability, which allows no cut-off point, indicates that
the entities are not significantly different enough in themselves to justify
a principled difference between observable and unobservable ones.
That is, it’s not necessarily significant to the nature of microscopic
entities that we cannot normally see them with the naked eye. That
is a limitation of human beings’ sensory apparatus which we can escape
through the use of instruments like microscopes. To argue that unobservables
are ontologically different from observables based solely on the fact that
we cannot observe them makes no sense. Are the limmitations of the
sensory powers of human beings really the determining factor of the reality
or the natrure of the existence of all entities in the universe?
This seems, to me, impossible. A tree falling in the forest does
make a sound, even if there is no one there to hear it. It makes
a sound because sound is a vibration of air molecules that does not depend
on the presence of human ears for its occurence. But this point leads
us to what is so great about human ears. They sense vibrations in
air molecules by amplifying and converting vibrations upon the ear drum,
allowing a causal interaction with the world that gives humans the ability
to form correct beliefs about states of affairs in the world. I will
return to the issue of causal interaction later.
Let me first restate just what the idea of a continuum between
observable and unobservable does for a credit-giving view. The indepence
and reality of the observable world is unproblematic. Indeed, barring
some kind of global skepticism--which I have elected not to argue against--it
is very difficult to deny. The continuum argument shows that the
ontological status of the observable world is contagious. That we
know it to be real means, if we think a little about the difficulty of
finding a good place to put the border between observable and unobservable,
it becomes clear that a radical change in ontological status between the
two is implausible. The change from “independent of human inquiry”
to “dependent on human agonistic activity (or any other social process)”
is just such a radical change.
Take as an example a small insect with compound eyes. Imagine
that the compound eyes are just large enough to be visible as tiny dots.
The individual eyelets cannot be observed with the naked eye. It
makes no sense to say that the observable eyes of the insect are real and
independent while the eyelets are not. The unobservable eyelets,
as constituent parts of the observable eyes, must surely have an independent
reality also. This is how the ontological status of the observable
world is contagious. But there is also an epistemological point to
be made here. Let’s say we wish to count the number of eyelets in
our insect’s compound eyes. We have established that the eyelets
have an independent reality and so they must have a determinate number.
We can count the larger, observable eyes to learn how many of them there
are. Our observation of the observable world is thereby established
as a source of knowledge about that world. The continuum argument,
with regard to observation, shows that a stark contrast between observation
of observable objects and (previously) unobservable objects is untenable.
We can learn about observables through observation, and given the continuum
between the two, we know that we can learn about ubobservables as well.
All we need is confidence in the reliability of the process. The
observable-to-observable check provides this, as do arguments presented
in the following section.
Technology, explainability, and the argument from coincidence
The continuum argument will only get us as far as the highest resolution
of instruments which work like microscopes and telescopes, with their gradually
increasing degrees of magnification. I have also suggested something
like it can be used to infer the observability of organisms in the past.
This “time-travel” form is limited to inference about the results of processes
which can be observed in a human lifetime. This leaves a lot to be
desired. Van Fraassen’s clear cases of unobservables still stand.
You can’t turn a microscope up high enough to look at an electron.
However, the continuum argument is bolstered by others.
Two related arguments are those from technology and explainability.
The technology argument is based on the manipulative success of the technology
involved in scientific instruments. This is the idea that technology,
the development and use of which is at least somewhat independent of scientific
theory, has a certain degree of recognizable power. The power of
technology independent of theory is evident in cases where the technology
is developed and used before the theoretical explanation comes along.
Of course, when a theoretical explanation does accompany powerful technology,
it strenthens the case for the accuracy of the instruments even more.
This is the explainability argument. It is based on the idea that
being able to explain the way an instrument works with the relevant scientific
theory is another reason to believe in the accuracy of a representation
yielded by the instrument.
Technology and explainability connect in a special way.
That the manipulative power of instruments and methods can be explained
by scientific theories is reason to believe that the theories are approximately
true. The move toward greater complexity and explanatory power over
the course of the history of science has been accompanied by more and more
powerful technology. We have a body of scientific theories which
have enabled the progress of technology, can explain the workings of the
technology, and also fit to a great degree with an enormous body of empirical
evidence. It would be a miracle indeed if those scientific theories
did not refer to the workings of the world in an approximately accurate
and steadily improving way.
Perhaps the most powerful of the arguments allied with the continuum
and explainability arguments is one which Ian Hacking calls the argument
from coincidence. It is similar to my thought experiment which shows
the independence of the observable world. The idea is that different
instruments, the technology of which depends on different parts of science,
reveal the same phenomena. Hacking cites the example of an electron
microscope showing constellations of dense bodies on red blood platelets.
The experimenter suspected that the dense bodies were artifacts of the
electron microscope equipment, and checked the same sample with a fluorescent
microscope. The light microscope revealed the same bodies in the
same constellations, verifying their independence from the electron microscopy
method. Examples of observing the same phenomena with different instrumentation
abound. They prove that each individual method is not arbitrary or
constructed. The similarity of results means that, for social constructivists
to prove that an eperimental result is constructed, they would have to
prove that every other method that might test the same phenomena would
also not only be constructed, but be constructed in a way that would yeild
the same results. This indicates a picture of science as something
more than isolated practices which seem to lend themselves to being viewed
as construced. If different, relatively isolated parts of science
indicate the same result, we are lead to a picture of science as one big,
extremely coherent social construction, one which acts a lot like an activity
that finds out about an independent, real world. As Hacking puts
it, “it would be a preposterous coincidence if two totally different kinds
of physical systems were to produce exactly the same arrangements of dots
on micrographs.”
To get back to observability, the argument from coincidence is
another good reason to believe in the accuracy of the representations of
scientific instruments. We can compare images across different methods,
which gives us faith in the methods and in the idea that the entities we
perceive with instruments act like entities we can observe without instruments.
Our increased confidence in the accuracy of instruments gives us reason
to believe that the representations they produce allow us to observe the
phenomena under study. That the phenomena can be consistently observed
in different ways is reason to believe in their independence from any of
the methods of observation. This is a general point, not one based
on the resolution of microscopes. The argument from coincidence is,
in itself, a reason to believe in the reality of the observed phenomena,
because of what it indicates about the possibility of the accuracy of our
observations. The power and reliability of instruments make the unobservable
observable. The observability of previously-unobservable phenomena
in different and accurate experimental set-ups gives us confidence in the
independence and reality of the phenomena in the same way as our observation
of ordinary objects gives us confidence in their independence.
I have tried to keep this discussion about observability general, but
the fact is that each instrument and each experimental set-up deserves
its own justification. I have sketched such a justification for microscopy,
with an implication that it should serve as a model for others. However,
the continuum strategy in microscopy is not promising for the justification
of a method like the use of bubble chambers in high energy physics.
But I have offered a combination of related arguments which should indicate
how to defend such a case. Showing the manipulative power of the
equipment involved in HEP is likely to be very powerful. Hacking
argues that using an electron as a tool in an experiment commits the experimenter
to believing in its reality. I contend that using a particle accelerator
commits the experimenter to believing in its manipulative power.
Although the technology argument with its emphasis on manipulative power
may only warrant something like instrumentalism, the explainability argument,
along with the well-known strategy of inference to the best explanation,
warrants belief in the reality of and the theories about the phenomena
observed with reliable instruments.
The continuum between observable and unobservable casts doubt
on our ability to draw a meaningful line--according to the criterion of
observability--which separates things which exist, or things we can know
and everything else. Neither the ontological distinction upon
which the empiricist depends nor the epistemological distinction upon which
the constructivist depends can reasonably be based on assessments of observability.
The consistency of the results of different scientific experiments and
the consistency between those results and the the relevant theories along
with the consistency of scientific theories with a body of technology which
has very real manipulative power is evidence for the fact that those theories
approximately accurately describe the phenomena to which they refer.
There is not enough space in the present project to elaborate a full defence
of this point, which would need to include answers to concerns about underdetermination,
the pessimistic meta-induction, and other complex issues. I
think these concerns can be answered. But the current project is
an answer to social constructivism, which contends that science proceeds
according to social factors, rather than input from an independent world.
All I really need to show is that science is not entirely controlled by
social factors and that the social forces that are present are not necessarily
damaging to its cognitive status. The next two sections are concerned
with these objectives.
Causal interaction
I have alluded to the idea that causal interaction is what’s so great
about human perception. We see because our eyes sense light which
is reflected or emitted by nearby objects. The way the light rays
are organized tells us about the object from which they come. Sense
perception can serve as evidence because it involves interacting with the
world in a way that allows the state of affairs in the world to affect
the character of the relevant belief. The use of instruments and
systematic experimentation to learn things we cannot with our unaided senses
and the limited empirical data gleaned in an ordinary individual’s life
are what’s so great about science. Of course the important part about
experimentation is just the same as in unaided sense perception; that the
state of affairs in the world affect the character of the beliefs formed.
This is what social constructivists argue doesn’t happen. Latour
and Woolgar contend that social processes control what becomes scientific
fact, and that “the effect of reality” is produced as a result of the solidification
of a fact. For them, there is no reality “out there” for beliefs
to be formed in accord with. I have argued that the observable world
is a ready example of reality “out there.” Observable objects can
be consistently perceived across different sense modalities, individuals,
and cultures. The behavior of observable objects is consistent in
many important respects and general laws predicting and explaining their
behavior can be formulated. This forces the constructivist to retreat
to the unobservable world, as Bloor does. But using observability
as a criterion for a distinction between real and not-real has also turned
out to be problematic. Noting the similarity of the unobservable
world to the observable leads us to recognizing that it exhibits a similar
reality and independence from human inquiry. The question remains
whether our inquiry allows us access to that world.
The extreme constructivist thesis about scientific inquiry is
that there is nothing about that inquiry which affords us access to the
workings of nature. This is a very strong claim, and the empirical
research done in microsociological case studies simply does not support
it. Latour and Woolgar’s third chapter, “The Construction of a Fact,”
mentions many assays, tests, and stages of experiment, and never shows
that any of them is inconclusive or suspect in any way. Indeed, without
getting into the relevant endocrinology--which they don’t--there is no
way to evaluate whether the experiments described interact with the world
in a way conducive to producing a true account. Surely some experiments
allow scientists to interact with nature in a very obvious way. In
genetics, a scientist may simply count the number of offspring with a certain
trait that are produced by parent organisms. Ordinary sense perception
may be an unproblematic method for such an experiment. Constructivism
has some difficulty showing that such measurements of observables are entirely
socially constructed, because of the ease and consistency of interaction
with the observable world. Furthermore, just as the arguments of
the above sections show the independence of unobservables by connecting
their behavior and measurement to that of observables, we can assume that
measurements of unobservables tend to afford genuine access to the relevant
state of affairs because we know that measurements of observables do.
The complete argument that a given experimental set-up involves
sufficient causal interaction with nature will depend on the instruments
used and the technology and theory behind them. Inasmuch as some
science does not use instruments and is based on measurements of observables,
it is impossible to occupy the position that all of science is socially
constructed. I hope the trouble with the observable/unobservable
distinction casts doubt on the possibility that all experiments which use
instruments yield socially constructed results as well. This point
is easy to make in the field of microscopy. But I must admit that
a complete defense of the stance that a bubble chamber allows causal interaction
with subatomic particles is not something I’m capable of. I
do not move from recognizing that to arguing that it is not something that
can be done--which is what Latour and Woolgar do when they depend on an
assumption of strangeness. I think that the physics and technology
in a bubble chamber can be explained in a way which should make us comfortable
with the idea that experiments in high energy physics do allow scientists
to interact with and observe particles. And that is exactly what
is so great about particle accelerators and bubble chambers. This
is a fact that probably seems so obvious to anyone who uses a particle
accelerator that it’s not worth mentioning. But philosophers tend
to doubt obvious facts like it. The recognition that instruments
allow causal interaction in a way analogous to simple sense perception
is just what we need to deny the extreme constructivist claim that there
is nothing about science which is not socially constructed. To prove
the extreme opposing claim that there is nothing about science that is
socially constructed would take more than an argument about the plausibility
of the accuracy of measurements of unobservables. But I won’t attempt
to do that. In fact, I don’t think it is possible. There are
social aspects of science. There are social factors that are good
for the cognitive success of science. This is the topic of my next
section.
Social factors in science
I recognize, along with the social constructivists, that science has
an important social element. I do not, however, agree with them that
this means that science is entirely social or that it does not do what
it claims to do. I think that science’s superior epistemic
status in our culture is warranted and that the socialness of science,
jarring though it may be to holders of the traditional view of science,
does not take away from that status. It seems that there are two
immediate strategies for the response of a holder of a credit-giving view
of science to the socialness of the activity. The first, and probably
most obvious, is to invoke a kind of god-of-the-gaps argument. This
is the idea that the social factors that we have admitted are present in
science only really affect elements of scientific practice that are irrelevant
to the cognitive output of the activity. This is basically no different
from the traditional defense against accusations of socialness.
Here I stand with the social constructivists and say that this position
is not tenable. But a credit-giving view need not depend on it.
Another strategy to present itself is the idea that the social aspects
of science are neither damaging nor irrelevant to its cognitive output,
but are positive forces, helping scientists find out about the world.
What does it take for a social process to be good for science?
The general criterion is, of course, the same as that for any process:
epistemic reliability. Reliable processes--that is, ones which tend
to lead to true beliefs--are exactly what is wanted in an activity concerned
with discovering truth. The reliability of scientific instruments
is what I tried to establish in my arguments concerning the observable/unobservable
distinction. This is just the kind of thing that needs to be shown
about social processes.
An analogy or two will be of help here. One set of social
processes often pointed to in studies of science consists of those which
influence the motivation of scientists and the reward processes that exist
in the practice of science. Scientists are apparently often motivated
by things other than a pure, noble pursuit of truth. They are motivated
by the desire for credit, fame, or even money. This does not, however,
mean that they do not attain truth. David Papineau offers a game
analogy. He says that few poker players are motivated by the
desire to conform to the rules of the game; they are much more likely to
be motivated by the desire to win money. But they are still playing
the game, following the rules, and when they win to earn money, they still
win. As Helen Longino quotes David Hull, “knowledge may be a by-product
of the activities that obtain the primary results (e.g., credit) desired
by scientists; but, because of the rules by which the game is played, it
is still a product.” When a scientist comes up with a good
theory in order to get famous, she still comes up with a good theory.
An even stronger case for the usefulness of social processes than showing
that ulterior motives don’t hurt is to show that elements of scientific
method may be significantly social and still be good for science.
Think of shooting free throws in basketball. Children playing in
school or at the park probably learn how to shoot free throws entirely
through social processes; they are likely to be concerned with doing it
in a way that looks good as much as anything else--probably a large motivating
factor will be the desire not to be made fun of by the other children.
But their techniques can be evaluated for whether they tend to make the
ball go into the goal or not. In this case, what “looks good” is
likely to correspond to what children see professional basketball players
doing. And what professional players do is likely to be good at making
the ball go through the hoop. So a method that is learned socially
and reinforced socially helps with the unsocial process of getting the
ball through the hoop. Indeed, to return to the issue of motivation,
the rules of the scientific community are such that--even assuming a scientist’s
motivation is solely to get famous--the best way to do that is to have
original ideas, careful methods, and repeatable results. These are
exactly the kinds of things we need to be present to make sure what’s being
done is good science.
Just what kind of social processes can the credit-giver admit are present
in science without having to worry about the epistemic status of science’s
cognitive output? We should find two basic categories. The
first consists of factors which facilitate evidential processes, and the
second consists of factors which can be more directly characterized as
evidential processes. In the first category, we find things like
fund allocation and specialization of labor. Laboratory science could
not exist without generous grants from universities, governments, foundations,
etc. Having enough money is necessary to building a particle accelerator,
and having a particle accelerator is necessary to creating evidential links
between limited human knowers and subatomic particles. Similarly,
as mentioned above, a particle accelerator could not work without a team
of many people, each assigned to different, specialized tasks. The
presence of obviously social factors like these and their importance to
science is easily acknowledged by the traditional view of science.
That they facilitate evidential processes is the obvious explanation for
their place in the practice of science, and they are not threatening to
a credit-giving view. Scientists’ motivations should also be placed
in this category. Scientists may be motivated entirely be the desire
to earn credit and respect in the relevant community, but because of the
way the standards are set up in that community, the best way to do that
is usually by doing good science. This is not to say that these factors
necessarily always lead to the best scientific results, but that they tend
to. The reliability of factors like these is based on the idea of
encouraging individuals or groups who show promise. That is, achieving
one significant result will lead to more funding and resources, which is
likely to lead to more significant results. This is a fine explanation
for why scientists are motivated by the desire for credit; it will become
a resource which they can invest in future research.
The second category of social factors in science consists of
those which act more directly as evidential processes. These are
the processes which foil the traditional strategy of using the social/evidential
distinction as the deciding factor in what should be counted as good science.
They are processes which are correctly identified as social but are used
in an evidential way in scientific practice. As in the first category,
this often comes down to the idea that individuals or groups who have produced
good results in the past will produce good results again. To put
it another way, credit is earned. As an example, take the prestige
of a particular laboratory group. This prestige increases the confidence
of others reading a new paper by the group that the findings the paper
reports are accurate. The prestige is a social factor, but it is
used by members of the community in the evidential process of deciding
about the status of a particular finding. Thus the prestige, which
is earned through the past production of good results, becomes evidence
for the accuracy of the newer result. This implies that some people
can be better at scientific inquiry than others, which has a clear enough
parallel with the idea that some people are better at ordinary sense perception
than others (certain people have, for instance, better vision than others).
Just as people can allow their perception of ordinary objects to be corrected
by others with better vision, so does the scientific community use discussion
and criticism of results to decide upon accurate representations.
Social constructivists suggest that the socialness of science
is something deeper than the easily-recognizable patterns of prestige alluded
to above. They argue that the most central and productive elements
of scientific practice cannot be considered purely evidential (that is,
unsocial). But the idea that even the most central aspects of science
are social need not be a threat to a credit-giving view. Helen Longino
has argued that the objectivity of science is dependent upon understanding
scientific inquiry as fundamentally social and that two central elements
to the production of scientific knowledge--observation and justificatory
reasoning--are significantly (and unproblematically) social.
Her discussions are not simply statements of these claims but explanations
of the way the socialness recognized bolsters the cognitive status of science.
Here the socialness of the processes involved is admitted and used to defend
the objectivity of science. Longino’s arguments tend to involve a
theme along the lines of “many knowers are better than one.” That
is, observation is social in that it is not simply the sense perception
of an individual, but an activity that is regular and intersubjectively
invariant. These are important aspects of the repeatability of experiments--that
anyone else in the same situation, or in contact with a relevantly similar
experimental set up would perceive the same results. When experimenters
check their results with colleagues and with the larger scientific community,
it is a social process, but one which helps guarantee the objectivity of
science.
Although Latour and Woolgar’s destruction of the social/evidential distinction
seems to be unwarranted, we have seen that the distinction is not very
helpful in thinking about science. Constructivists, despite their
denials, usually destroy the social/evidential dichotomy in favor of the
social. That is, they say that we cannot show that the two sides
of the dichotomy are sufficiently different, and--in light of the traditional
dependence on the unsocialness of science for its cognitive status--we
must conclude that science is merely a social construction. I have
discussed the problems with this approach above. A holder of a credit-giving
view sufficiently informed by the useful insights of social constructivism
might be tempted to break down the social/evidential distinction in favor
of the evidential instead. I don’t think this is the right way to
think about the issue. We can tell the difference between social
and evidential categories of processes, and we can tell when a process
fits into both categories. But the spirit of the suggestion is right.
Let’s keep in mind that the subject of the discussion is the
epistemic status of science. If we really stick to the point, what
matters is not how social any given process is, but how evidential it is.
I have offered examples of social processes which can still be evaluated
for their effectiveness in the relevant domain--basketball or describing
the world. That is what should be focused on in either case: the
effectiveness in the relevant domain. If a process is good at creating
accurate descriptions of the world, why should we care how social it is?
This is, rather than a breakdown of the social/evidential distinction in
favor of either side, more like a setting aside of the distinction and
the recognition that what is important to thinking about science is evaluating
the epistemic effectiveness of the processes involved. It should
be noted that social constructivists like Latour and Woolgar and Knorr-Cetina
only attempt to evaluate the socialness of elements of scientific practice,
not their epistemic effectiveness. Considering the debunking tone
of their projects and the fact that their conclusions are aimed at the
cognitive status of science, this is clearly the wrong focus. Discovering
and describing social aspects of science is, of course, still an interesting
pursuit. My point is that studies of science which do not take epistemic
evaluation as part of the data-gathering process should make epistemic
evaluations in their conclusions.
What should really be done in studies of science is evaluations
of elements of scientific practice for how well they afford human beings
contact with the workings of the world. To do this they must be causally
responsive to elements of the world and reliable in terms of yielding accurate
representations. If these conditions are satisfied, then science
is not just a social construction (or set of many constructions), but rather
an activity with some real connection to an independent world. I
have not attempted to pin down nature of that connection in this project.
I hope to have shown the superiority of a credit-giving view over any strong
form of social constructivism. A credit-giving view, in order to
be a serious contender, however, should be informed by the socialness of
science and should not make the same mistakes the traditional view does--mistakes
which social constructivism calls attention to. My umbrella category
of “credit-giving views” leaves room for versions of both empiricism and
scientific realism, and picking out the best one of these is a natural
follow-up to this project. My treatment of the relationship between
unobservables and observables will give the reader some clue as to which
I favor. I think that empiricism is an ultimately unsatisfying way
to give science credit, and that realism is the most promising view of
science. I have avoided articulating a defence of realism over empiricism
or other credit-giving views because that is not within the scope of the
present project. The intent of this project is to diffuse the apparent
threat to realism from social constructivism. I have done so by discussing
the superiority of credit-giving views in general--of which my own scientific
realism is one. The (purposely vague) picture of science that should
come out of this project is one of science as an activity that is social
in important ways. However, the socialness of science is not, prima
facie, threatening to cognitive status. Claims that science is “just”
a social construction can be refuted by showing that the practice of science
allows the state of affairs in the world to be at least one determining
factor to the character of scientific theories. The remaining, uncontested
socialness of science does not necessarily make even “socially constructed”
science have no connection with states of affairs in the world. Social
factors, too, can be reliable in terms of leading scientists to accurate
representations.