Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz
Born: 1 July 1646 in Leipzig,
Saxony (now Germany)
Died: 14 Nov 1716 in Hannover, Hanover (now Germany)
Gottfried
Leibniz was the son of Friedrich Leibniz, a professor of moral
philosophy at Leipzig. Friedrich Leibniz :-
...was evidently a competent though not original
scholar, who devoted his time to his offices and to his family
as a pious, Christian father.
Leibniz's mother was Catharina Schmuck, the
daughter of a lawyer and Friedrich Leibniz's third wife. However,
Friedrich Leibniz died when Leibniz was only six years old
and he was brought up by his mother. Certainly Leibniz learnt
his moral and religious values from her which would play an
important role in his life and philosophy.
At the age of seven, Leibniz entered the Nicolai
School in Leipzig. Although he was taught Latin at school,
Leibniz had taught himself far more advanced Latin and some
Greek by the age of 12. He seems to have been motivated by
wanting to read his father's books. As he progressed through
school he was taught Aristotle's logic and theory of categorising
knowledge. Leibniz was clearly not satisfied with Aristotle's
system and began to develop his own ideas on how to improve
on it. In later life Leibniz recalled that at this time he
was trying to find orderings on logical truths which, although
he did not know it at the time, were the ideas behind rigorous
mathematical proofs. As well as his school work, Leibniz studied
his father's books. In particular he read metaphysics books
and theology books from both Catholic and Protestant writers.
In 1661, at the age of fourteen, Leibniz entered
the University of Leipzig. It may sound today as if this were
a truly exceptionally early age for anyone to enter university,
but it is fair to say that by the standards of the time he
was quite young but there would be others of a similar age.
He studied philosophy, which was well taught at the University
of Leipzig, and mathematics which was very poorly taught.
Among the other topics which were included in this two year
general degree course were rhetoric, Latin, Greek and Hebrew.
He graduated with a bachelors degree in 1663 with a thesis
De Principio Individui (On the Principle of the Individual)
which:-
... emphasised the existential value of the
individual, who is not to be explained either by matter alone
or by form alone but rather by his whole being.
In this there is the beginning of his notion
of "monad". Leibniz then went to Jena to spend the
summer term of 1663.
At Jena the professor of mathematics was Erhard
Weigel but Weigel was also a philosopher and through him Leibniz
began to understand the importance of the method of mathematical
proof for subjects such as logic and philosophy. Weigel believed
that number was the fundamental concept of the universe and
his ideas were to have considerable influence of Leibniz.
By October 1663 Leibniz was back in Leipzig starting his studies
towards a doctorate in law. He was awarded his Master's Degree
in philosophy for a dissertation which combined aspects of
philosophy and law studying relations in these subjects with
mathematical ideas that he had learnt from Weigel. A few days
after Leibniz presented his dissertation, his mother died.
After being awarded a bachelor's degree in
law, Leibniz worked on his habilitation in philosophy. His
work was to be published in 1666 as Dissertatio de arte combinatoria
(Dissertation on the combinatorial art). In this work Leibniz
aimed to reduce all reasoning and discovery to a combination
of basic elements such as numbers, letters, sounds and colours.
Despite his growing reputation and acknowledged
scholarship, Leibniz was refused the doctorate in law at Leipzig.
It is a little unclear why this happened. It is likely that,
as one of the younger candidates and there only being twelve
law tutorships available, he would be expected to wait another
year. However, there is also a story that the Dean's wife
persuaded the Dean to argue against Leibniz, for some unexplained
reason. Leibniz was not prepared to accept any delay and he
went immediately to the University of Altdorf where he received
a doctorate in law in February 1667 for his dissertation De
Casibus Perplexis (On Perplexing Cases).
Leibniz
declined the promise of a chair at Altdorf because he had
very different things in view. He served as secretary to the
Nuremberg alchemical society for a while (see [187]) then
he met Baron Johann Christian von Boineburg. By November 1667
Leibniz was living in Frankfurt, employed by Boineburg. During
the next few years Leibniz undertook a variety of different
projects, scientific, literary and political. He also continued
his law career taking up residence at the courts of Mainz
before 1670. One of his tasks there, undertaken for the Elector
of Mainz, was to improve the Roman civil law code for Mainz
but:-
Leibniz was also occupied by turns as Boineburg's
secretary, assistant, librarian, lawyer and advisor, while
at the same time a personal friend of the Baron and his family.
Boineburg
was a Catholic while Leibniz was a Lutheran but Leibniz had
as one of his lifelong aims the reunification of the Christian
Churches and:-
... with Boineburg's encouragement, he drafted
a number of monographs on religious topics, mostly to do with
points at issue between the churches...
Another
of Leibniz's lifelong aims was to collate all human knowledge.
Certainly he saw his work on Roman civil law as part of this
scheme and as another part of this scheme, Leibniz tried to
bring the work of the learned societies together to coordinate
research. Leibniz began to study motion, and although he had
in mind the problem of explaining the results of Wren and
Huygens on elastic collisions, he began with abstract ideas
of motion. In 1671 he published Hypothesis Physica Nova (New
Physical Hypothesis). In this work he claimed, as had Kepler,
that movement depends on the action of a spirit. He communicated
with Oldenburg, the secretary of the Royal Society of London,
and dedicated some of his scientific works to The Royal Society
and the Paris Academy. Leibniz was also in contact with Carcavi,
the Royal Librarian in Paris. As Ross explains in:-
Although Leibniz's interests were clearly
developing in a scientific direction, he still hankered after
a literary career. All his life he prided himself on his poetry
(mostly Latin), and boasted that he could recite the bulk
of Virgil's "Aeneid" by heart. During this time
with Boineburg he would have passed for a typical late Renaissance
humanist.
Leibniz wished to visit Paris to make more
scientific contacts. He had begun construction of a calculating
machine which he hoped would be of interest. He formed a political
plan to try to persuade the French to attack Egypt and this
proved the means of his visiting Paris. In 1672 Leibniz went
to Paris on behalf of Boineburg to try to use his plan to
divert Louis XIV from attacking German areas. His first object
in Paris was to make contact with the French government but,
while waiting for such an opportunity, Leibniz made contact
with mathematicians and philosophers there, in particular
Arnauld and Malebranche, discussing with Arnauld a variety
of topics but particularly church reunification.
In Paris Leibniz studied mathematics and physics
under Christiaan Huygens beginning in the autumn of 1672.
On Huygens' advice, Leibniz read Saint-Vincent's work on summing
series and made some discoveries of his own in this area.
Also in the autumn of 1672, Boineburg's son was sent to Paris
to study under Leibniz which meant that his financial support
was secure. Accompanying Boineburg's son was Boineburg's nephew
on a diplomatic mission to try to persuade Louis XIV to set
up a peace congress. Boineburg died on 15 December but Leibniz
continued to be supported by the Boineburg family.
In January 1673 Leibniz and Boineburg's nephew
went to England to try the same peace mission, the French
one having failed. Leibniz visited the Royal Society, and
demonstrated his incomplete calculating machine. He also talked
with Hooke, Boyle and Pell. While explaining his results on
series to Pell, he was told that these were to be found in
a book by Mouton. The next day he consulted Mouton's book
and found that Pell was correct. At the meeting of the Royal
Society on 15 February, which Leibniz did not attend, Hooke
made some unfavourable comments on Leibniz's calculating machine.
Leibniz returned to Paris on hearing that the Elector of Mainz
had died. Leibniz realised that his knowledge of mathematics
was less than he would have liked so he redoubled his efforts
on the subject.
The Royal Society of London elected Leibniz
a fellow on 19 April 1673. Leibniz met Ozanam and solved one
of his problems. He also met again with Huygens who gave him
a reading list including works by Pascal, Fabri, Gregory,
Saint-Vincent, Descartes and Sluze. He began to study the
geometry of infinitesimals and wrote to Oldenburg at the Royal
Society in 1674. Oldenburg replied that Newton and Gregory
had found general methods. Leibniz was, however, not in the
best of favours with the Royal Society since he had not kept
his promise of finishing his mechanical calculating machine.
Nor was Oldenburg to know that Leibniz had changed from the
rather ordinary mathematician who visited London, into a creative
mathematical genius. In August 1675 Tschirnhaus arrived in
Paris and he formed a close friendship with Leibniz which
proved very mathematically profitable to both.
It was during this period in Paris that Leibniz
developed the basic features of his version of the calculus.
In 1673 he was still struggling to develop a good notation
for his calculus and his first calculations were clumsy. On
21 November 1675 he wrote a manuscript using the f(x) dx notation
for the first time. In the same manuscript the product rule
for differentiation is given. By autumn 1676 Leibniz discovered
the familiar d(xn) = nxn-1dx for both integral and fractional
n.
Newton wrote a letter to Leibniz, through
Oldenburg, which took some time to reach him. The letter listed
many of Newton's results but it did not describe his methods.
Leibniz replied immediately but Newton, not realising that
his letter had taken a long time to reach Leibniz, thought
he had had six weeks to work on his reply. Certainly one of
the consequences of Newton's letter was that Leibniz realised
he must quickly publish a fuller account of his own methods.
Newton wrote a second letter to Leibniz on
24 October 1676 which did not reach Leibniz until June 1677
by which time Leibniz was in Hanover. This second letter,
although polite in tone, was clearly written by Newton believing
that Leibniz had stolen his methods. In his reply Leibniz
gave some details of the principles of his differential calculus
including the rule for differentiating a function of a function.
Newton was to claim, with justification, that
..not a single previously unsolved problem
was solved ...
by Leibniz's approach but the formalism was
to prove vital in the latter development of the calculus.
Leibniz never thought of the derivative as a limit. This does
not appear until the work of d'Alembert.
Leibniz would have liked to have remained
in Paris in the Academy of Sciences, but it was considered
that there were already enough foreigners there and so no
invitation came. Reluctantly Leibniz accepted a position from
the Duke of Hanover, Johann Friedrich, of librarian and of
Court Councillor at Hanover. He left Paris in October 1676
making the journey to Hanover via London and Holland. The
rest of Leibniz's life, from December 1676 until his death,
was spent at Hanover except for the many travels that he made.
His
duties at Hanover:-
... as librarian were onerous, but fairly
mundane: general administration, purchase of new books and
second-hand libraries, and conventional cataloguing.
He
undertook a whole collection of other projects however. For
example one major project begun in 1678-79 involved draining
water from the mines in the Harz mountains. His idea was to
use wind power and water power to operate pumps. He designed
many different types of windmills, pumps, gears but :-
... every one of these projects ended in failure.
Leibniz himself believed that this was because of deliberate
obstruction by administrators and technicians, and the worker's
fear that technological progress would cost them their jobs.
In 1680 Duke Johann Friedrich died and his
brother Ernst August became the new Duke. The Harz project
had always been difficult and it failed by 1684. However Leibniz
had achieved important scientific results becoming one of
the first people to study geology through the observations
he compiled for the Harz project. During this work he formed
the hypothesis that the Earth was at first molten.
Another of Leibniz's great achievements in
mathematics was his development of the binary system of arithmetic.
He perfected his system by 1679 but he did not publish anything
until 1701 when he sent the paper Essay d'une nouvelle science
des nombres to the Paris Academy to mark his election to the
Academy. Another major mathematical work by Leibniz was his
work on determinants which arose from his developing methods
to solve systems of linear equations. Although he never published
this work in his lifetime, he developed many different approaches
to the topic with many different notations being tried out
to find the one which was most useful. An unpublished paper
dated 22 January 1684 contains very satisfactory notation
and results.
Leibniz continued to perfect his metaphysical
system in the 1680s attempting to reduce reasoning to an algebra
of thought. Leibniz published Meditationes de Cognitione,
Veritate et Ideis (Reflections on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas)
which clarified his theory of knowledge. In February 1686,
Leibniz wrote his Discours de métaphysique (Discourse
on Metaphysics).
Another major project which Leibniz undertook,
this time for Duke Ernst August, was writing the history of
the Guelf family, of which the House of Brunswick was a part.
He made a lengthy trip to search archives for material on
which to base this history, visiting Bavaria, Austria and
Italy between November 1687 and June 1690. As always Leibniz
took the opportunity to meet with scholars of many different
subjects on these journeys. In Florence, for example, he discussed
mathematics with Viviani who had been Galileo's last pupil.
Although Leibniz published nine large volumes of archival
material on the history of the Guelf family, he never wrote
the work that was commissioned.
In 1684 Leibniz published details of his differential
calculus in Nova Methodus pro Maximis et Minimis, itemque
Tangentibus... in Acta Eruditorum, a journal established in
Leipzig two years earlier. The paper contained the familiar
d notation, the rules for computing the derivatives of powers,
products and quotients. However it contained no proofs and
Jacob Bernoulli called it an enigma rather than an explanation.
In 1686 Leibniz published, in Acta Eruditorum,
a paper dealing with the integral calculus with the first
appearance in print of the notation.
Newton's Principia appeared the following
year. Newton's 'method of fluxions' was written in 1671 but
Newton failed to get it published and it did not appear in
print until John Colson produced an English translation in
1736. This time delay in the publication of Newton's work
resulted in a dispute with Leibniz.
Another
important piece of mathematical work undertaken by Leibniz
was his work on dynamics. He criticised Descartes' ideas of
mechanics and examined what are effectively kinetic energy,
potential energy and momentum. This work was begun in 1676
but he returned to it at various times, in particular while
he was in Rome in 1689. It is clear that while he was in Rome,
in addition to working in the Vatican library, Leibniz worked
with members of the Accademia. He was elected a member of
the Accademia at this time. Also while in Rome he read Newton's
Principia. His two part treatise Dynamica studied abstract
dynamics and concrete dynamics and is written in a somewhat
similar style to Newton's Principia. Ross writes in :-
... although Leibniz was ahead of his time
in aiming at a genuine dynamics, it was this very ambition
that prevented him from matching the achievement of his rival
Newton. ... It was only by simplifying the issues... that
Newton succeeded in reducing them to manageable proportions.
Leibniz put much energy into promoting scientific
societies. He was involved in moves to set up academies in
Berlin, Dresden, Vienna, and St Petersburg. He began a campaign
for an academy in Berlin in 1695, he visited Berlin in 1698
as part of his efforts and on another visit in 1700 he finally
persuaded Friedrich to found the Brandenburg Society of Sciences
on 11 July. Leibniz was appointed its first president, this
being an appointment for life. However, the Academy was not
particularly successful and only one volume of the proceedings
were ever published. It did lead to the creation of the Berlin
Academy some years later.
Other attempts by Leibniz to found academies
were less successful. He was appointed as Director of a proposed
Vienna Academy in 1712 but Leibniz died before the Academy
was created. Similarly he did much of the work to prompt the
setting up of the St Petersburg Academy, but again it did
not come into existence until after his death.
It
is no exaggeration to say that Leibniz corresponded with most
of the scholars in Europe. He had over 600 correspondents.
Among the mathematicians with whom he corresponded was Grandi.
The correspondence started in 1703, and later concerned the
results obtained by putting x = 1 into 1/(1+x) = 1 - x + x2
- x3 + .... Leibniz also corresponded with Varignon on this
paradox. Leibniz discussed logarithms of negative numbers
with Johann Bernoulli.
In 1710 Leibniz published Théodicée
a philosophical work intended to tackle the problem of evil
in a world created by a good God. Leibniz claims that the
universe had to be imperfect, otherwise it would not be distinct
from God. He then claims that the universe is the best possible
without being perfect. Leibniz is aware that this argument
looks unlikely - surely a universe in which nobody is killed
by floods is better than the present one, but still not perfect.
His argument here is that the elimination of natural disasters,
for example, would involve such changes to the laws of science
that the world would be worse. In 1714 Leibniz wrote Monadologia
which synthesised the philosophy of his earlier work, the
Théodicée.
Much of the mathematical activity of Leibniz's
last years involved the priority dispute over the invention
of the calculus. In 1711 he read the paper by Keill in the
Transactions of the Royal Society of London which accused
Leibniz of plagiarism. Leibniz demanded a retraction saying
that he had never heard of the calculus of fluxions until
he had read the works of Wallis. Keill replied to Leibniz
saying that the two letters from Newton, sent through Oldenburg,
had given:-
... pretty plain indications... whence Leibniz
derived the principles of that calculus or at least could
have derived them.
Leibniz wrote again to the Royal Society asking
them to correct the wrong done to him by Keill's claims. In
response to this letter the Royal Society set up a committee
to pronounce on the priority dispute. It was totally biased,
not asking Leibniz to give his version of the events. The
report of the committee, finding in favour of Newton, was
written by Newton himself and published as Commercium epistolicum
near the beginning of 1713 but not seen by Leibniz until the
autumn of 1714. He learnt of its contents in 1713 in a letter
from Johann Bernoulli, reporting on the copy of the work brought
from Paris by his nephew Nicolaus(I) Bernoulli. Leibniz published
an anonymous pamphlet Charta volans setting out his side in
which a mistake by Newton in his understanding of second and
higher derivatives, spotted by Johann Bernoulli, is used as
evidence of Leibniz's case.
The
argument continued with Keill who published a reply to Charta
volans. Leibniz refused to carry on the argument with Keill,
saying that he could not reply to an idiot. However, when
Newton wrote to him directly, Leibniz did reply and gave a
detailed description of his discovery of the differential
calculus. From 1715 up until his death Leibniz corresponded
with Samuel Clarke, a supporter of Newton, on time, space,
freewill, gravitational attraction across a void and other
topics.
In
Leibniz is described as follows:-
Leibniz was a man of medium height with a
stoop, broad-shouldered but bandy-legged, as capable of thinking
for several days sitting in the same chair as of travelling
the roads of Europe summer and winter. He was an indefatigable
worker, a universal letter writer (he had more than 600 correspondents),
a patriot and cosmopolitan, a great scientist, and one of
the most powerful spirits of Western civilisation.
Ross,
in , points out that Leibniz's legacy may have not been quite
what he had hoped for:-
It is ironical that one so devoted to the
cause of mutual understanding should have succeeded only in
adding to intellectual chauvinism and dogmatism. There is
a similar irony in the fact that he was one of the last great
polymaths - not in the frivolous sense of having a wide general
knowledge, but in the deeper sense of one who is a citizen
of the whole world of intellectual inquiry. He deliberately
ignored boundaries between disciplines, and lack of qualifications
never deterred him from contributing fresh insights to established
specialisms. Indeed, one of the reasons why he was so hostile
to universities as institutions was because their faculty
structure prevented the cross-fertilisation of ideas which
he saw as essential to the advance of knowledge and of wisdom.
The irony is that he was himself instrumental in bringing
about an era of far greater intellectual and scientific specialism,
as technical advances pushed more and more disciplines out
of the reach of the intelligent layman and amateur.
- J J O'Connor and E F Robertson |