The
Value Controversy
A
reply to G.A. Cohen
The
central scientific discovery in the realm of economics by Karl Marx was
the theory of Surplus-Value. The
theory of surplus-value argued that the origin of the capitalist profit
was in fact the exploited labour-power of the worker.
It was Marx’s understanding that once the dynamics of capitalist
exploitation were made clear to the workers, all illusions in the
capitalist system would melt like snow at the coming of spring. On the basis of this scientific understanding, workers would
rise up and build a socialist society.
It
is no surprise, therefore, that ideological attacks have been made on the
body of Marxism from all different directions and flanks, from the most
philosophical and abstract, to the most political and concrete.
Similarly bourgeois economists the world over have spent much of
their time in an attempt to refute the theory of surplus-value.
In this paper I shall be critically analysing one such clumsy
attack by an author named G. A. Cohen.
This paper will work systematically through Cohen’s argument
refuting his claims chronologically.
Mr.
Cohen fires the opening shot by informing the reader that “the
relationship between the theory of value and the concept of exploitation
is one of mutual irrelevance.”
Mr.
Cohen says that “the central claim of the labour theory of value is that
magnitude of value is determined by socially necessary labour time”,
“but a stipulate definition of a technical term is not a theory, and
when value is defined as socially necessary labour time, it cannot also be
a central theoretical claim of the labour theory that socially necessary
labour time determines value”.
First,
it is incorrect to say that the central claim of the labour theory of
value is that magnitude of value is determined by socially necessary
labour time. The central
claim of Marx’s use of the labour theory of value is that the concept of
value can explain the movement of the laws of commodity production.
Second,
‘value is socially necessary labour-time’ is a central a priori axiom
of the labour theory of value. The
method of scientific discovery does not exclude the presupposition of an a
priori axiom or the pre-definition of a central concept.
The science lies in being able to show how this concept helps to
explain the movement of the entire complex phenomenon.
Marx captured this understanding in a letter to Kugelmann 11 July
1868:
The
nonsense about the necessity of proving the concept of value arises from
complete ignorance both of the subject dealt and of the method of science.
…
The
science consists precisely in working out how
the law of value operates. So
that if one wanted at the very beginning to “explain” all the
phenomena which apparently contradict that law, one would have to give the
science before
the science.
In
section (2) Cohen contends that the word ‘exploitation’ should not be
used in relation to surplus-value. He
argues that this phrase ‘denotes a kind of injustice’ and that
Marxists are ‘purely scientific’ without ‘moral content’.
First,
it is incorrect to place the concept of exploitation outside the ambit of
science a priori.
It implies that science has nothing to say about relations of
domination or oppression? Science
is not antithetical to questions with respect to relations of domination,
subordination, exploitation, oppression or alienation.
In the Thesis of Feuerbach Marx criticised mechanical materialism
for its failure to analyse and develop the subjective side of humans.
The
chief defect of all hitherto existing materialism (that of Feuerbach
included) is that the thing, reality, sensuousness, is conceived only in
the form of the object or of contemplation, but not as sensuous
human activity, practice, not subjectively. Hence, in
contradistinction to materialism, the active side was developed
abstractly by idealism -- which, of course, does not know real, sensuous
activity as such.
Second,
this practice of placing science outside
relations of exploitation confuses the issue between science and
morality. For Marxists
science lays bare the basis of any particular morality.
In other words, science shows that morality is by definition class
morality. Marx was opposed to
the ‘mere moral
condemnation’ of capitalism (as the Young Hegelians were fond of doing)
because such critiques revealed nothing about the profound dynamics of the
system. Marx went on to prove that the economic dynamics of the
capitalist system inevitably
lead to the birth and development of a revolutionary exploited class
interested in the overthrow of the capitalist system.
Therefore, Marxism is not above
classes, such a position can not logically exist.
Marxists base their morality on
science. The so called
science of Cohen that stands outside
of morality is a continuation of mechanical materialism that fails to
look at the subjective side of humans as objective activity.
Cohen
makes three short rhetorical flourishes perhaps to undermine the
confidence of the reader. He
says “that an explicit normative premise is not stated” with respect
to the term ‘exploitation’. One
must ask how much more explicit does the normative premise have to be?
Marx quite clearly says that the transfer of surplus from the
working class to the capitalist class is ‘exploitation’.
Next Cohen states that it is ‘disputed’ whether the labourer
“is forced by his
propertylessness, to work for the capitalist”.
One must ask whether Cohen suggesting that workers would live happy
and healthy lives by not being
employed. That there is no compulsion in a capitalist system to seek employment.
Clearly those who dispute such things have never had to face the sting of
unemployment. Cohen says that
an explicit definition of the
working class or the capitalist class is not given in Capital. In fact it is quite clear that people who earn their living
purely by selling their labour-power are proletariats and people who earn
their living off the labour-power
of workers are capitalists. But
these arguments are just embellishments of Cohen’s main arguments
against the labour theory of value.
Cohen
attempts to ‘destroy’ the labour theory of value by pointing out that
value does not correspond to exchange value.
He tries to show that a rapid change in the socially necessary
labour time in the production of a commodity will cause a discrepancy
between the exchange-value and labour-value.
He says:
Suppose
there is a use-value a, which
was produced in the past, when things such as a
could come into being only through labour, but that labour is no
longer required to produce such a thing as a
to appear. Then according to
the labour theory of value, a is valueless, despite the labour
‘embodied’ in it.
Cohen
has really outdone himself in terms of profundity. There is no need to delve into Capital Volume III to untie
this knot (although Marx deals with it in great detail in that volume),
one simply has to turn the popular pamphlet written by Marx and Engels
entitled Wage Labour and Capital
to answer the above question.
By
what is the price of a commodity determined ?
By
competition between buyers and sellers, by the relations of inquiry to
delivery, of demand to supply.
…
And
if price is determined by the relations between supply and demand, what
determines the relations between supply and demand?
…
We
see how capital continually migrates in and out of the domain of one
industry into that of another. High
prices bring too great an immigration and low prices too great an
emigration.
…
We
have just seen how the fluctuations of supply and demand continually bring
the price of a commodity back to the cost of production.
…
The
determination of price by the cost of production is equivalent to the
determination of price by labour time necessary for the manufacture of a
commodity, of the cost of production consists of 1) raw materials and
depreciation of instruments, that is, of industrial products the
production of which has cost a certain amount of labour days and which,
therefore, represent a certain amount of labour time, and 2) of direct
labour, the measure of which is, precisely, time.
It
becomes clear from the above quotation that exchange-value corresponds to
labour-value only through the mechanism of supply and demand, the movement
of prices, and the resultant movement of capital between branches of
industry. The fact that at a
particular point in time exchange-value does not correspond to labour-value
is not problematic to Marx’s theory but is axiomatic to it. When
exchange-value does not correspond to labour-value, capital is reallocated
from one branch of industry to another.
In other words, exchange-value corresponds to labour-value only as
a tendency of capital to
equalise the rate of profit among different branches of production.
Therefore,
in the example pointed out by Cohen one can see that people will stop
producing a since it will be
freely available. Through the
movement of capital away from the branch of industry that formerly
produced a, its price will
become zero, and come to reflect the new labour-value of a.
But
Cohen wishes to address a slightly different point. He argues that value does not correspond to the amount of
value contained in the
commodity. He acknowledges
that Marx was aware of his argument.
For example he quotes Marx as saying:
What
determines value is not the amount of labour-time incorporated in
products, but rather the amount of labour-time currently necessary.
The
value of every commodity … is determined not by the necessary labour-time
contained in it, but by the social labour-time required for its
reproduction.”
In
the latter part of section (5) Cohen artificially bifurcates ‘Marx’s
argument’ into the strict doctrine,
and the popular doctrine and
takes great pleasure in pouncing upon the popular
doctrine. Then he tells
us of a mixed formulation that
Marxists use to bring ‘in line’ the popular
and the strict doctrine. There is absolutely no
point in defending this so called popular,
or mixed doctrines, in so far as they exist, they seem to be
purely a construct of Cohen’s own mind, and therefore, wholly irrelevant
to Marx’s labour theory of
value. The fact that Cohen
takes great pleasure in pouncing upon the shadows of his own brain one can
only attribute to a fetish on his own part.
Cohen argues that ‘Marxists’ assume that:
To
put it in simpler terms, Cohen is saying that Marxists (not Marx) assume
that the socially necessary labour-time contained
in a commodity is equal to the socially necessary labour-time
necessary for its reproduction.
This assertion is only true if there is no change in technology
between the time a commodity is created and the time it is sold in the
market.
Thus,
Cohen correctly points out that the so called popular understanding that “value is determined by the socially
necessary labour-time contained in
a commodity”, is incorrect. In
fact and in accordance with Marx’s correct formulation, value is the
socially necessary labour-time for the reproduction
of a commodity.
It
still stands to test whether Cohen can prove that there is a discrepancy
(apart from the temporal fluctuations of demand and supply) between the
exchange-value of a commodity and the socially necessary labour-time for
its reproduction? This task Cohen does not attempt but this is precisely the
task he must attempt if he is to disprove Marx’s
labour theory of value and not a popular
interpretation of that theory of value.
In a word, Cohen must argue with Marx, not with the straw-man he
has constructed of Marx’s argument.
One
can empirically verify that the tendency of capital to equalise the rate
of profit dominates the movement of prices via the circuit of supply and
demand. Therefore, prices
have a tendency to converge, owing to the resultant reallocation of
capital via supply and demand, in the direction of the socially necessary
labour-time for the reproduction of that commodity.
That in essence means that the socially necessary labour-time for
reproduction determines the value and via the supply and demand functions
the exchange-value.
Miraculously Cohen takes great pleasure in
announcing with the air of indignant intellectual superiority that “We
may therefore take it that labour does not create value, whether or not
the labour theory of value is true.”
In fact, G.A. Cohen has only helped us understand how the popular
interpretation of Marxism leaves open a loophole that is easily
remediable. He has not done anything at all to disprove Marx’s
elaboration of the labour theory of value.
----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------