The
Truth is Out There!
Because
it Certainly Isn’t in Here
The
last decade of the twentieth century is commonly referred to as “the age
of confusion.” Naturally,
certain people have a direct interest in maintaining confusion; confusion
bolsters the status quo. On
the other hand, the oppressed peoples of the world require clarity;
clarity is a revolutionary force.
In
this paper I will be arguing in favour of a materialist epistemology.
Considering the breadth and depth of the subject (the subject spans
the length of European twentieth century thought from Hegel and Marx to
Foucoult and Habermas), this paper can only be a very modest attempt, or
merely a starting point to untangle the epistemological debate in the
modern world.
What
is Epistemology?
Although
starting with a dictionary definition of a concept is not only a cliché
but can also be problematic, in so far as it excludes other ways of
understanding a process, nonetheless, for lack of a better place to begin
and in order to find some common ground from where to begin, I choose to
start from the Oxford English Dictionary’s definition of epistemology as
“the theory or science of the methods or grounds of knowledge” (Pg.
338). Therefore, epistemology is a theory of knowledge and poses
the question “what is the basis of knowledge?” or more simply “how
do we know, what we think we know?”
Epistemology
is distinct from methodology. Methodology
is simply the manner in which the study of a question is arranged.
That is, what questions are asked first, what evidences are
compiled in order to solve the question, and so on.
Every study, therefore, already presupposes both an epistemology and a
methodology. However, the
distinction is important to underscore the possibility of two
diametrically opposed methodologies and theories, agreeing on a common
epistemology (for example, Marxism and Neo-liberalism).
Similarly, two diametrically opposed theories and conclusions, may
agree on the same methodology and epistemology (for example, Smith’s
economic model and Marx’s economic model).
Post-Modernism
and Epistemology
The
debate regarding epistemology has found renewed interest owing to the
popularity at the end of the cold war of the post-modernist / post-structuralist
critique of modernity. Therefore,
perhaps it is better to start with the end and reconstruct the beginning.
Post-modernism
is mainly inspired by the writings of figures such as Michel Foucault,
Jacques Derrida, and Richard Rorty. Although
it is difficult to “pin down” post-modernism, one can certainly
discern certain themes that are repeated and associated with
post-modernism.
Firstly,
post-modernism is a rejection of the notion that a “Grand Narrative”
can explain history. It
argues that the very idea of a “Grand Narrative” is itself a product
of notions from the European Enlightenment, and therefore, an idea that is
culturally and historically specific.
Post-modernists argue that the entire project of the Enlightenment
(including Liberalism, Marxism, and Science) has failed, and therefore,
proves the impossibility of constructing a grand narrative.
Secondly,
and this naturally follows from the first, post-modernism is a rejection
of notions of “Progress”, “Science”, “Objectivity”, and
“Rationality”. These
notions are merely social constructs and paradigms. The result is a deep
epistemological doubt about any claims to science, rationality,
objectivity, or value free theory.
Third,
as opposed to a scientific untangling of the objective world,
post-modernism seeks to deconstruct the role of discourse, culture, and
language as a realm of oppression, struggle, and emancipation.
This methodology of deconstructing language and concepts is
referred to as post-structuralism. Culture
and language studies, therefore, is deeply influenced by
post-structuralism.
The
original thinkers of post-modernism, such as Foucault, mean for this new
paradigm to be used as a tool for emancipation. For example, Foucoult claims that “power is implicated in
all knowledge systems”, and therefore, “knowledge is a tool for
resisting power”. The
conclusion is that those who are interested in resisting power must create
their own “knowledge system” in order to resist power.
Thus, the mushrooming of post-Marxism and post-feminism, feminist
science owes itself, in no small measure, to the influence of
post-modernism.
Is
there a Truth? Is there an objective world?
To
refute post-modernism in a comprehensive manner would require substantial
research; nonetheless, one can show logically that the epistemological
basis of post-modernism is self-contradictory.
Let us start with the axiom “There is no universal truth.”
In this axiom the “truth” is synonymous with “objective
science” because objective science claims to be “the truth”.
On
closer examination it becomes apparent that the axiom that “there is no
universal truth” is itself a universal axiom.
In other words, the above axiom can be rewritten as “the
universal truth is, that there is no universal truth.” This does not
change the original axiom; it merely elaborates what was hidden within the
original axiom. Now if the
former axiom is true than the latter cannot be true; the latter can only
exist as an expression of the former.
In other words, the paradigm is hopelessly fraught with
self-contradiction and is a philosophical and logical absurdity.
In a word, implicit in the original axiom is claim about a
universal truth and explicit in the axiom is a claim that there is no such
thing as a universal truth. From
the aforementioned analysis one can only reach the conclusion that all
theories that seek to challenge the possibility of an objective
epistemology have a self-contradictory foundation.
Lets
see how this understanding works with respect to Thomas Kuhn’s critique
of science in the book The Structure
of Scientific Revolution. Kuhn
argues, much like the post-modernists, that humans understand the world in
the context of a paradigm. For
a period of time, the paradigm helps to solve certain problems at a
particular period in history. During
this period, challenges to the paradigm are considered mistakes made in
the application of the paradigm and not as a fundamental flaw in the basis
of the paradigm itself. After
an indeterminate period, anomalies build up and lead to a crisis in
thought because the paradigm can no longer explain these irregularities.
At this point in time, a new revolutionary paradigm arises until
eventually it also becomes the norm.
This process is repeated in a cycle through the history of science. Kuhn further asserts that this entire process of the creation
and death of paradigms (scientific or otherwise) has no objective basis.
Paradigms are “are incommensurable” he says and there is no objective
basis to distinguish the correctness or the incorrectness of one paradigm
with respect to another; that there is no entity in common between two
paradigms; that there is no basis for comparison; or, for that matter,
even of comprehension.
If the above argument is correct, especially if the latter part is held
to be true, then one ends up with the same aforementioned logical
absurdity. It follows from
Kuhn’s own argument that that there is no basis for determining whether
Kuhn’s paradigm of “incommensurable paradigms” is correct or
incorrect. How would we know? Since,
as Kuhn asserts, there is no “objective basis” or
“commensurability” between paradigms, there is then also no basis to
judge this alleged “incommensurability” itself.
At the most Kuhn can assert he himself has built yet another
incommensurable paradigm. Naturally,
at this point one lapses into self-contradiction.
Kuhn’s particular paradigm, which by definition has to be
incommensurable like all paradigms, is not incommensurable.
This is because Kuhn asserts that his particular paradigm is “the
paradigm” that explains the very creation and death of other paradigms.
Given the fact that all paradigms are incommensurable, can one
build a universal paradigm to explain other paradigms?
To put it more simply, to assert as a universal paradigm that all
paradigms are incommensurable is a self-contradiction and a logical
absurdity. It is no different
from the logical error made in the first instant.
Can
Science Be Objective and Non-Ideological?
The
answers to the above questions can be derived from the above stated
argument. It follows
logically from the above argument that science is objective in the sense
that there is an objective world that a scientist attempts to study. Scientists attempt to discern the objective laws of
development of the natural and social world. The subjectivity of the
scientist may distort the practice science.
However, this distortion, in and of itself, would not change the
objective existence of the world or even the possibility of studying it
scientifically and objectively. In
other words, this subjectivity would constitute an example of the poor
application of the principles of science.
In conclusion, the world exists objectively irrespective of our
degree of comprehension of it and science is the attempt to study that
objective world.
However,
a note of caution is necessary while asserting that science is objective.
While there is no doubt that science is objective, this does not
imply that science is neutral to questions of power.
For example, a scientific analysis of capitalist conditions reveals
relations of exploitation. Therefore,
the scientific discovery of surplus-value favoured the development of the
working class movement. In
conclusion, while science is objective, it is never neutral or
value-neutral in relation to questions of power.
If
one defines ideology as the “systematic distortion of the truth in order
to legitimise the power of one group of people over other people”, then
science is the opposite of ideology and is non-ideological. Science is the opposite of ideology.
Conclusion
From
the above argument we can conclude that any theory that seeks to limit the
possibility of an all-embracing theory, is itself an all-embracing theory
and therefore self-contradictory. In
other words, it is itself what it professes to reject.
The
inevitable result of accepting a non-scientific epistemology in relation
to the study of society is that one lapses into complete relativism and
subjectivism. The methodology
of post-structuralism is the inevitable outcome of a non-scientific
epistemology. Post-structuralism
allows one the “intellectual freedom”, in other words subjectivity, in
which one can freely interpret and reinterpret discourse without any
reference to objective reality,
to the structure of society, to
the economic base, or to class.
The fact that a few post-structuralists refer to class in their
critique does not disprove my point.
It merely illustrates it with more force because these references
to class are not the foundation and do not act as a unit of analysis of
post-structuralism. These
references are peripheral or supplementary references and do not follow as
a logical necessity.
Post-structuralism is the flip side of bourgeois hypocrisy.
There is no doubt that bourgeois politicians and academics distort
science by defining terms in order to bolster their policies.
The post-structuralists redefine them in a subjective manner to
favour themselves. Neither
group is interested in a disinterested analysis of their own objective
position with respect to the rest of society.
The post-structuralist epistemological and methodological approach
predisposes them to grave subjective errors.
Mostly this error assumes the inability to distinguish between form
and content. The form of two
things might be exactly the same but they may be different in content or
essence. Since post-structuralists concentrate on the super-structure
in terms of form (e.g. language) they are unable to see what objective
position the subject acquires in a system of power relationships.
For example, the discourse of a socialist trade-union leader, and a
fascist leader might be the same in form (for example, both may talk in
militaristic terms). However,
they play diametrically opposite roles in relation to the class struggle.
Concentrating on the form predisposes one to the error of
subjective interpretation (which may also become a thin shiny veneer to
conceal bourgeois prejudice). They
attribute fundamental qualities to the form (the subjective) and do not
see that form is a vehicle for the transmission of content (the
objective).
Post-modernism
and post-sructuralism are modern forms of idealism. It is not a coincidence that they share the hatred for
science that was a hallmark of pre-capitalist idealism. Post-modernism and post-structuralism is the “theoretical
machine breaking” of the modern world.
In the early decades of the industrial revolution workers thought
that their oppression was the product of machines and not of the social
relations of production. They
therefore, broke machines in an attempt to roll back history.
But of course this was a primitive form of rebellion and did not
work.
Similarly,
post-modernism and post-structuralism is machine breaking by the
intellectual (without the consequences that workers faced for their
rebellion). But curiously,
the attack by post-modernists and post-structuralists on science, which is
lauded as the greatest things since the Enlightenment, is to the
particular taste of the decaying bourgeoisie of metropolitan countries.
The decaying and counter-revolutionary bourgeoisie of the
metropolitan centres supports both reaction and idealism in third world
countries in the form of “religious intolerance”, and idealism in its
modern post-modernist and post-structuralist form in first world
countries. Both these form,
in their particular context, help to obscure the clarity so necessary for
a emancipation. The
post-modernists, centred in European society, are themselves the product
of a failed and despondent generation of sixties “radicals” seeking to
reintegrate themselves into the bourgeois world.
In this context, their modern form of idealism is extremely useful
to the bourgeoisie for it obscures the objective basis of exploitation and
the necessary steps (especially organisational and political) to solve the
problems of the world today. It
is not a coincidence that the post-modernists and post-structuralists are
firmly rooted in the social studies department of the educational
institutes of the West. The
post-structuralists perform a great service to the capitalist world by
substituting the “word” itself as a revolutionary “act”.
The familiar expression of “theory itself as action” in this
context (and only in this particular context), translates in terms of
praxis into a rather benign and harmless preoccupation on the part of
certain academics to interpret and reinterpret discourse.
In
conclusion, social science must begin with and can only begin with the
premise that the world exists as an objective and understandable entity.
An analysis is scientific in the measure that it accords with
reality and, in doing so, informs practice.
Furthermore, the post-modern critique of materialist epistemology
(“science” is a construct)
is self-contradictory subjectivism. Post-modernism
and post-structuralism are supported by the reactionary bourgeoisie of
Europe to befuddle and confuse the revolutionary potential of students and
prevent the emergence of a revolutionary socialist intelligentsia.
These ideas play a retrogressive role in the development of class
struggle and history.
Bibliography
Kuhn,
Thomas Samuel (1996), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago University Press.
Marx,
Karl (1970). A Contribution to the
critique of political economy. London: Lawrence and Wishart.
McLellan,
G. (1989). Marxism, pluralism and beyond. Oxford: Polity.
Oxford English Dictionary,
(1989), Oxford Clarendon P.
Smith, S.; Booth, K.; Zalewski, M.; Jahn, Beate, International
Theory: Positivism and Beyond,
------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------