Metaphysics
By Aristotle
Part 1
"WE have stated what is the substance of sensible things,
dealing in the treatise on physics with matter, and later with
the substance which has actual existence. Now since our inquiry
is whether there is or is not besides the sensible substances
any which is immovable and eternal, and, if there is, what it
is, we must first consider what is said by others, so that, if
there is anything which they say wrongly, we may not be liable
to the same objections, while, if there is any opinion common
to them and us, we shall have no private grievance against ourselves
on that account; for one must be content to state some points
better than one's predecessors, and others no worse.
"Two
opinions are held on this subject; it is said that the objects
of mathematics-i.e. numbers and lines and the like-are substances,
and again that the Ideas are substances. And (1) since some recognize
these as two different classes-the Ideas and the mathematical
numbers, and (2) some recognize both as having one nature, while
(3) some others say that the mathematical substances are the
only substances, we must consider first the objects of mathematics,
not qualifying them by any other characteristic-not asking, for
instance, whether they are in fact Ideas or not, or whether they
are the principles and substances of existing things or not,
but only whether as objects of mathematics they exist or not,
and if they exist, how they exist. Then after this we must separately
consider the Ideas themselves in a general way, and only as far
as the accepted mode of treatment demands; for most of the points
have been repeatedly made even by the discussions outside our
school, and, further, the greater part of our account must finish
by throwing light on that inquiry, viz. when we examine whether
the substances and the principles of existing things are numbers
and Ideas; for after the discussion of the Ideas this remans
as a third inquiry.
"If the objects of mathematics exist,
they must exist either in sensible objects, as some say, or separate
from sensible objects (and this also is said by some); or if
they exist in neither of these ways, either they do not exist,
or they exist only in some special sense. So that the subject
of our discussion will be not whether they exist but how they
exist.
Part 2
"That it is impossible for mathematical objects to exist
in sensible things, and at the same time that the doctrine in
question is an artificial one, has been said already in our discussion
of difficulties we have pointed out that it is impossible for
two solids to be in the same place, and also that according to
the same argument the other powers and characteristics also should
exist in sensible things and none of them separately. This we
have said already. But, further, it is obvious that on this theory
it is impossible for any body whatever to be divided; for it
would have to be divided at a plane, and the plane at a line,
and the line at a point, so that if the point cannot be divided,
neither can the line, and if the line cannot, neither can the
plane nor the solid. What difference, then, does it make whether
sensible things are such indivisible entities, or, without being
so themselves, have indivisible entities in them? The result
will be the same; if the sensible entities are divided the others
will be divided too, or else not even the sensible entities can
be divided.
"But, again, it is not possible that such
entities should exist separately. For if besides the sensible
solids there are to be other solids which are separate from them
and prior to the sensible solids, it is plain that besides the
planes also there must be other and separate planes and points
and lines; for consistency requires this. But if these exist,
again besides the planes and lines and points of the mathematical
solid there must be others which are separate. (For incomposites
are prior to compounds; and if there are, prior to the sensible
bodies, bodies which are not sensible, by the same argument the
planes which exist by themselves must be prior to those which
are in the motionless solids. Therefore these will be planes
and lines other than those that exist along with the mathematical
solids to which these thinkers assign separate existence; for
the latter exist along with the mathematical solids, while the
others are prior to the mathematical solids.) Again, therefore,
there will be, belonging to these planes, lines, and prior to
them there will have to be, by the same argument, other lines
and points; and prior to these points in the prior lines there
will have to be other points, though there will be no others
prior to these. Now (1) the accumulation becomes absurd; for
we find ourselves with one set of solids apart from the sensible
solids; three sets of planes apart from the sensible planes-those
which exist apart from the sensible planes, and those in the
mathematical solids, and those which exist apart from those in
the mathematical solids; four sets of lines, and five sets of
points. With which of these, then, will the mathematical sciences
deal? Certainly not with the planes and lines and points in the
motionless solid; for science always deals with what is prior.
And (the same account will apply also to numbers; for there will
be a different set of units apart from each set of points, and
also apart from each set of realities, from the objects of sense
and again from those of thought; so that there will be various
classes of mathematical numbers.
"Again, how is it possible
to solve the questions which we have already enumerated in our
discussion of difficulties? For the objects of astronomy will
exist apart from sensible things just as the objects of geometry
will; but how is it possible that a heaven and its parts-or anything
else which has movement-should exist apart? Similarly also the
objects of optics and of harmonics will exist apart; for there
will be both voice and sight besides the sensible or individual
voices and sights. Therefore it is plain that the other senses
as well, and the other objects of sense, will exist apart; for
why should one set of them do so and another not? And if this
is so, there will also be animals existing apart, since there
will be senses.
"Again, there are certain mathematical
theorems that are universal, extending beyond these substances.
Here then we shall have another intermediate substance separate
both from the Ideas and from the intermediates,-a substance which
is neither number nor points nor spatial magnitude nor time.
And if this is impossible, plainly it is also impossible that
the former entities should exist separate from sensible things.
"And, in general, conclusion contrary alike to the truth
and to the usual views follow, if one is to suppose the objects
of mathematics to exist thus as separate entities. For because
they exist thus they must be prior to sensible spatial magnitudes,
but in truth they must be posterior; for the incomplete spatial
magnitude is in the order of generation prior, but in the order
of substance posterior, as the lifeless is to the living.
"Again,
by virtue of what, and when, will mathematical magnitudes be
one? For things in our perceptible world are one in virtue of
soul, or of a part of soul, or of something else that is reasonable
enough; when these are not present, the thing is a plurality,
and splits up into parts. But in the case of the subjects of
mathematics, which are divisible and are quantities, what is
the cause of their being one and holding together?
"Again,
the modes of generation of the objects of mathematics show that
we are right. For the dimension first generated is length, then
comes breadth, lastly depth, and the process is complete. If,
then, that which is posterior in the order of generation is prior
in the order of substantiality, the solid will be prior to the
plane and the line. And in this way also it is both more complete
and more whole, because it can become animate. How, on the other
hand, could a line or a plane be animate? The supposition passes
the power of our senses.
"Again, the solid is a sort
of substance; for it already has in a sense completeness. But
how can lines be substances? Neither as a form or shape, as the
soul perhaps is, nor as matter, like the solid; for we have no
experience of anything that can be put together out of lines
or planes or points, while if these had been a sort of material
substance, we should have observed things which could be put
together out of them.
"Grant, then, that they are prior
in definition. Still not all things that are prior in definition
are also prior in substantiality. For those things are prior
in substantiality which when separated from other things surpass
them in the power of independent existence, but things are prior
in definition to those whose definitions are compounded out of
their definitions; and these two properties are not coextensive.
For if attributes do not exist apart from the substances (e.g.
a 'mobile' or a pale'), pale is prior to the pale man in definition,
but not in substantiality. For it cannot exist separately, but
is always along with the concrete thing; and by the concrete
thing I mean the pale man. Therefore it is plain that neither
is the result of abstraction prior nor that which is produced
by adding determinants posterior; for it is by adding a determinant
to pale that we speak of the pale man.
"It has, then,
been sufficiently pointed out that the objects of mathematics
are not substances in a higher degree than bodies are, and that
they are not prior to sensibles in being, but only in definition,
and that they cannot exist somewhere apart. But since it was
not possible for them to exist in sensibles either, it is plain
that they either do not exist at all or exist in a special sense
and therefore do not 'exist' without qualification. For 'exist'
has many senses.
Part 3
"For just as the universal propositions of mathematics
deal not with objects which exist separately, apart from extended
magnitudes and from numbers, but with magnitudes and numbers,
not however qua such as to have magnitude or to be divisible,
clearly it is possible that there should also be both propositions
and demonstrations about sensible magnitudes, not however qua
sensible but qua possessed of certain definite qualities. For
as there are many propositions about things merely considered
as in motion, apart from what each such thing is and from their
accidents, and as it is not therefore necessary that there should
be either a mobile separate from sensibles, or a distinct mobile
entity in the sensibles, so too in the case of mobiles there
will be propositions and sciences, which treat them however not
qua mobile but only qua bodies, or again only qua planes, or
only qua lines, or qua divisibles, or qua indivisibles having
position, or only qua indivisibles. Thus since it is true to
say without qualification that not only things which are separable
but also things which are inseparable exist (for instance, that
mobiles exist), it is true also to say without qualification
that the objects of mathematics exist, and with the character
ascribed to them by mathematicians. And as it is true to say
of the other sciences too, without qualification, that they deal
with such and such a subject-not with what is accidental to it
(e.g. not with the pale, if the healthy thing is pale, and the
science has the healthy as its subject), but with that which
is the subject of each science-with the healthy if it treats
its object qua healthy, with man if qua man:-so too is it with
geometry; if its subjects happen to be sensible, though it does
not treat them qua sensible, the mathematical sciences will not
for that reason be sciences of sensibles-nor, on the other hand,
of other things separate from sensibles. Many properties attach
to things in virtue of their own nature as possessed of each
such character; e.g. there are attributes peculiar to the animal
qua female or qua male (yet there is no 'female' nor 'male' separate
from animals); so that there are also attributes which belong
to things merely as lengths or as planes. And in proportion as
we are dealing with things which are prior in definition and
simpler, our knowledge has more accuracy, i.e. simplicity. Therefore
a science which abstracts from spatial magnitude is more precise
than one which takes it into account; and a science is most precise
if it abstracts from movement, but if it takes account of movement,
it is most precise if it deals with the primary movement, for
this is the simplest; and of this again uniform movement is the
simplest form.
"The same account may be given of harmonics
and optics; for neither considers its objects qua sight or qua
voice, but qua lines and numbers; but the latter are attributes
proper to the former. And mechanics too proceeds in the same
way. Therefore if we suppose attributes separated from their
fellow attributes and make any inquiry concerning them as such,
we shall not for this reason be in error, any more than when
one draws a line on the ground and calls it a foot long when
it is not; for the error is not included in the premisses.
"Each
question will be best investigated in this way-by setting up
by an act of separation what is not separate, as the arithmetician
and the geometer do. For a man qua man is one indivisible thing;
and the arithmetician supposed one indivisible thing, and then
considered whether any attribute belongs to a man qua indivisible.
But the geometer treats him neither qua man nor qua indivisible,
but as a solid. For evidently the properties which would have
belonged to him even if perchance he had not been indivisible,
can belong to him even apart from these attributes. Thus, then,
geometers speak correctly; they talk about existing things, and
their subjects do exist; for being has two forms-it exists not
only in complete reality but also materially.
"Now since
the good and the beautiful are different (for the former always
implies conduct as its subject, while the beautiful is found
also in motionless things), those who assert that the mathematical
sciences say nothing of the beautiful or the good are in error.
For these sciences say and prove a great deal about them; if
they do not expressly mention them, but prove attributes which
are their results or their definitions, it is not true to say
that they tell us nothing about them. The chief forms of beauty
are order and symmetry and definiteness, which the mathematical
sciences demonstrate in a special degree. And since these (e.g.
order and definiteness) are obviously causes of many things,
evidently these sciences must treat this sort of causative principle
also (i.e. the beautiful) as in some sense a cause. But we shall
speak more plainly elsewhere about these matters.
Part 4
"So much then for the objects of mathematics; we have
said that they exist and in what sense they exist, and in what
sense they are prior and in what sense not prior. Now, regarding
the Ideas, we must first examine the ideal theory itself, not
connecting it in any way with the nature of numbers, but treating
it in the form in which it was originally understood by those
who first maintained the existence of the Ideas. The supporters
of the ideal theory were led to it because on the question about
the truth of things they accepted the Heraclitean sayings which
describe all sensible things as ever passing away, so that if
knowledge or thought is to have an object, there must be some
other and permanent entities, apart from those which are sensible;
for there could be no knowledge of things which were in a state
of flux. But when Socrates was occupying himself with the excellences
of character, and in connexion with them became the first to
raise the problem of universal definition (for of the physicists
Democritus only touched on the subject to a small extent, and
defined, after a fashion, the hot and the cold; while the Pythagoreans
had before this treated of a few things, whose definitions-e.g.
those of opportunity, justice, or marriage-they connected with
numbers; but it was natural that Socrates should be seeking the
essence, for he was seeking to syllogize, and 'what a thing is'
is the starting-point of syllogisms; for there was as yet none
of the dialectical power which enables people even without knowledge
of the essence to speculate about contraries and inquire whether
the same science deals with contraries; for two things may be
fairly ascribed to Socrates-inductive arguments and universal
definition, both of which are concerned with the starting-point
of science):-but Socrates did not make the universals or the
definitions exist apart: they, however, gave them separate existence,
and this was the kind of thing they called Ideas. Therefore it
followed for them, almost by the same argument, that there must
be Ideas of all things that are spoken of universally, and it
was almost as if a man wished to count certain things, and while
they were few thought he would not be able to count them, but
made more of them and then counted them; for the Forms are, one
may say, more numerous than the particular sensible things, yet
it was in seeking the causes of these that they proceeded from
them to the Forms. For to each thing there answers an entity
which has the same name and exists apart from the substances,
and so also in the case of all other groups there is a one over
many, whether these be of this world or eternal.
"Again,
of the ways in which it is proved that the Forms exist, none
is convincing; for from some no inference necessarily follows,
and from some arise Forms even of things of which they think
there are no Forms. For according to the arguments from the sciences
there will be Forms of all things of which there are sciences,
and according to the argument of the 'one over many' there will
be Forms even of negations, and according to the argument that
thought has an object when the individual object has perished,
there will be Forms of perishable things; for we have an image
of these. Again, of the most accurate arguments, some lead to
Ideas of relations, of which they say there is no independent
class, and others introduce the 'third man'.
"And in
general the arguments for the Forms destroy things for whose
existence the believers in Forms are more zealous than for the
existence of the Ideas; for it follows that not the dyad but
number is first, and that prior to number is the relative, and
that this is prior to the absolute-besides all the other points
on which certain people, by following out the opinions held about
the Forms, came into conflict with the principles of the theory.
"Again, according to the assumption on the belief in
the Ideas rests, there will be Forms not only of substances but
also of many other things; for the concept is single not only
in the case of substances, but also in that of non-substances,
and there are sciences of other things than substance; and a
thousand other such difficulties confront them. But according
to the necessities of the case and the opinions about the Forms,
if they can be shared in there must be Ideas of substances only.
For they are not shared in incidentally, but each Form must be
shared in as something not predicated of a subject. (By 'being
shared in incidentally' I mean that if a thing shares in 'double
itself', it shares also in 'eternal', but incidentally; for 'the
double' happens to be eternal.) Therefore the Forms will be substance.
But the same names indicate substance in this and in the ideal
world (or what will be the meaning of saying that there is something
apart from the particulars-the one over many?). And if the Ideas
and the things that share in them have the same form, there will
be something common: for why should '2' be one and the same in
the perishable 2's, or in the 2's which are many but eternal,
and not the same in the '2 itself' as in the individual 2? But
if they have not the same form, they will have only the name
in common, and it is as if one were to call both Callias and
a piece of wood a 'man', without observing any community between
them.
"But if we are to suppose that in other respects
the common definitions apply to the Forms, e.g. that 'plane figure'
and the other parts of the definition apply to the circle itself,
but 'what really is' has to be added, we must inquire whether
this is not absolutely meaningless. For to what is this to be
added? To 'centre' or to 'plane' or to all the parts of the definition?
For all the elements in the essence are Ideas, e.g. 'animal'
and 'two-footed'. Further, there must be some Ideal answering
to 'plane' above, some nature which will be present in all the
Forms as their genus.
Part 5
"Above all one might discuss the question what in the
world the Forms contribute to sensible things, either to those
that are eternal or to those that come into being and cease to
be; for they cause neither movement nor any change in them. But
again they help in no wise either towards the knowledge of other
things (for they are not even the substance of these, else they
would have been in them), or towards their being, if they are
not in the individuals which share in them; though if they were,
they might be thought to be causes, as white causes whiteness
in a white object by entering into its composition. But this
argument, which was used first by Anaxagoras, and later by Eudoxus
in his discussion of difficulties and by certain others, is very
easily upset; for it is easy to collect many and insuperable
objections to such a view.
"But, further, all other things
cannot come from the Forms in any of the usual senses of 'from'.
And to say that they are patterns and the other things share
in them is to use empty words and poetical metaphors. For what
is it that works, looking to the Ideas? And any thing can both
be and come into being without being copied from something else,
so that, whether Socrates exists or not, a man like Socrates
might come to be. And evidently this might be so even if Socrates
were eternal. And there will be several patterns of the same
thing, and therefore several Forms; e.g. 'animal' and 'two-footed',
and also 'man-himself', will be Forms of man. Again, the Forms
are patterns not only of sensible things, but of Forms themselves
also; i.e. the genus is the pattern of the various forms-of-a-genus;
therefore the same thing will be pattern and copy.
"Again,
it would seem impossible that substance and that whose substance
it is should exist apart; how, therefore, could the Ideas, being
the substances of things, exist apart?
"In the Phaedo
the case is stated in this way-that the Forms are causes both
of being and of becoming. Yet though the Forms exist, still things
do not come into being, unless there is something to originate
movement; and many other things come into being (e.g. a house
or a ring) of which they say there are no Forms. Clearly therefore
even the things of which they say there are Ideas can both be
and come into being owing to such causes as produce the things
just mentioned, and not owing to the Forms. But regarding the
Ideas it is possible, both in this way and by more abstract and
accurate arguments, to collect many objections like those we
have considered.
Part 6
"Since we have discussed these points, it is well to
consider again the results regarding numbers which confront those
who say that numbers are separable substances and first causes
of things. If number is an entity and its substance is nothing
other than just number, as some say, it follows that either (1)
there is a first in it and a second, each being different in
species,-and either (a) this is true of the units without exception,
and any unit is inassociable with any unit, or (b) they are all
without exception successive, and any of them are associable
with any, as they say is the case with mathematical number; for
in mathematical number no one unit is in any way different from
another. Or (c) some units must be associable and some not; e.g.
suppose that 2 is first after 1, and then comes 3 and then the
rest of the number series, and the units in each number are associable,
e.g. those in the first 2 are associable with one another, and
those in the first 3 with one another, and so with the other
numbers; but the units in the '2-itself' are inassociable with
those in the '3-itself'; and similarly in the case of the other
successive numbers. And so while mathematical number is counted
thus-after 1, 2 (which consists of another 1 besides the former
1), and 3 which consists of another 1 besides these two), and
the other numbers similarly, ideal number is counted thus-after
1, a distinct 2 which does not include the first 1, and a 3 which
does not include the 2 and the rest of the number series similarly.
Or (2) one kind of number must be like the first that was named,
one like that which the mathematicians speak of, and that which
we have named last must be a third kind.
"Again, these
kinds of numbers must either be separable from things, or not
separable but in objects of perception (not however in the way
which we first considered, in the sense that objects of perception
consists of numbers which are present in them)-either one kind
and not another, or all of them.
"These are of necessity
the only ways in which the numbers can exist. And of those who
say that the 1 is the beginning and substance and element of
all things, and that number is formed from the 1 and something
else, almost every one has described number in one of these ways;
only no one has said all the units are inassociable. And this
has happened reasonably enough; for there can be no way besides
those mentioned. Some say both kinds of number exist, that which
has a before and after being identical with the Ideas, and mathematical
number being different from the Ideas and from sensible things,
and both being separable from sensible things; and others say
mathematical number alone exists, as the first of realities,
separate from sensible things. And the Pythagoreans, also, believe
in one kind of number-the mathematical; only they say it is not
separate but sensible substances are formed out of it. For they
construct the whole universe out of numbers-only not numbers
consisting of abstract units; they suppose the units to have
spatial magnitude. But how the first 1 was constructed so as
to have magnitude, they seem unable to say.
"Another
thinker says the first kind of number, that of the Forms, alone
exists, and some say mathematical number is identical with this.
"The case of lines, planes, and solids is similar. For
some think that those which are the objects of mathematics are
different from those which come after the Ideas; and of those
who express themselves otherwise some speak of the objects of
mathematics and in a mathematical way-viz. those who do not make
the Ideas numbers nor say that Ideas exist; and others speak
of the objects of mathematics, but not mathematically; for they
say that neither is every spatial magnitude divisible into magnitudes,
nor do any two units taken at random make 2. All who say the
1 is an element and principle of things suppose numbers to consist
of abstract units, except the Pythagoreans; but they suppose
the numbers to have magnitude, as has been said before. It is
clear from this statement, then, in how many ways numbers may
be described, and that all the ways have been mentioned; and
all these views are impossible, but some perhaps more than others.
Part 7
"First, then, let us inquire if the units are associable
or inassociable, and if inassociable, in which of the two ways
we distinguished. For it is possible that any unity is inassociable
with any, and it is possible that those in the 'itself' are inassociable
with those in the 'itself', and, generally, that those in each
ideal number are inassociable with those in other ideal numbers.
Now (1) all units are associable and without difference, we get
mathematical number-only one kind of number, and the Ideas cannot
be the numbers. For what sort of number will man-himself or animal-itself
or any other Form be? There is one Idea of each thing e.g. one
of man-himself and another one of animal-itself; but the similar
and undifferentiated numbers are infinitely many, so that any
particular 3 is no more man-himself than any other 3. But if
the Ideas are not numbers, neither can they exist at all. For
from what principles will the Ideas come? It is number that comes
from the 1 and the indefinite dyad, and the principles or elements
are said to be principles and elements of number, and the Ideas
cannot be ranked as either prior or posterior to the numbers.
"But (2) if the units are inassociable, and inassociable
in the sense that any is inassociable with any other, number
of this sort cannot be mathematical number; for mathematical
number consists of undifferentiated units, and the truths proved
of it suit this character. Nor can it be ideal number. For 2
will not proceed immediately from 1 and the indefinite dyad,
and be followed by the successive numbers, as they say '2,3,4'
for the units in the ideal are generated at the same time, whether,
as the first holder of the theory said, from unequals (coming
into being when these were equalized) or in some other way-since,
if one unit is to be prior to the other, it will be prior also
to 2 the composed of these; for when there is one thing prior
and another posterior, the resultant of these will be prior to
one and posterior to the other. Again, since the 1-itself is
first, and then there is a particular 1 which is first among
the others and next after the 1-itself, and again a third which
is next after the second and next but one after the first 1,-so
the units must be prior to the numbers after which they are named
when we count them; e.g. there will be a third unit in 2 before
3 exists, and a fourth and a fifth in 3 before the numbers 4
and 5 exist.-Now none of these thinkers has said the units are
inassociable in this way, but according to their principles it
is reasonable that they should be so even in this way, though
in truth it is impossible. For it is reasonable both that the
units should have priority and posteriority if there is a first
unit or first 1, and also that the 2's should if there is a first
2; for after the first it is reasonable and necessary that there
should be a second, and if a second, a third, and so with the
others successively. (And to say both things at the same time,
that a unit is first and another unit is second after the ideal
1, and that a 2 is first after it, is impossible.) But they make
a first unit or 1, but not also a second and a third, and a first
2, but not also a second and a third. Clearly, also, it is not
possible, if all the units are inassociable, that there should
be a 2-itself and a 3-itself; and so with the other numbers.
For whether the units are undifferentiated or different each
from each, number must be counted by addition, e.g. 2 by adding
another 1 to the one, 3 by adding another 1 to the two, and similarly.
This being so, numbers cannot be generated as they generate them,
from the 2 and the 1; for 2 becomes part of 3 and 3 of 4 and
the same happens in the case of the succeeding numbers, but they
say 4 came from the first 2 and the indefinite which makes it
two 2's other than the 2-itself; if not, the 2-itself will be
a part of 4 and one other 2 will be added. And similarly 2 will
consist of the 1-itself and another 1; but if this is so, the
other element cannot be an indefinite 2; for it generates one
unit, not, as the indefinite 2 does, a definite 2.
"Again,
besides the 3-itself and the 2-itself how can there be other
3's and 2's? And how do they consist of prior and posterior units?
All this is absurd and fictitious, and there cannot be a first
2 and then a 3-itself. Yet there must, if the 1 and the indefinite
dyad are to be the elements. But if the results are impossible,
it is also impossible that these are the generating principles.
"If the units, then, are differentiated, each from each,
these results and others similar to these follow of necessity.
But (3) if those in different numbers are differentiated, but
those in the same number are alone undifferentiated from one
another, even so the difficulties that follow are no less. E.g.
in the 10-itself their are ten units, and the 10 is composed
both of them and of two 5's. But since the 10-itself is not any
chance number nor composed of any chance 5's--or, for that matter,
units--the units in this 10 must differ. For if they do not differ,
neither will the 5's of which the 10 consists differ; but since
these differ, the units also will differ. But if they differ,
will there be no other 5's in the 10 but only these two, or will
there be others? If there are not, this is paradoxical; and if
there are, what sort of 10 will consist of them? For there is
no other in the 10 but the 10 itself. But it is actually necessary
on their view that the 4 should not consist of any chance 2's;
for the indefinite as they say, received the definite 2 and made
two 2's; for its nature was to double what it received.
"Again,
as to the 2 being an entity apart from its two units, and the
3 an entity apart from its three units, how is this possible?
Either by one's sharing in the other, as 'pale man' is different
from 'pale' and 'man' (for it shares in these), or when one is
a differentia of the other, as 'man' is different from 'animal'
and 'two-footed'.
"Again, some things are one by contact,
some by intermixture, some by position; none of which can belong
to the units of which the 2 or the 3 consists; but as two men
are not a unity apart from both, so must it be with the units.
And their being indivisible will make no difference to them;
for points too are indivisible, but yet a pair of them is nothing
apart from the two.
"But this consequence also we must
not forget, that it follows that there are prior and posterior
2 and similarly with the other numbers. For let the 2's in the
4 be simultaneous; yet these are prior to those in the 8 and
as the 2 generated them, they generated the 4's in the 8-itself.
Therefore if the first 2 is an Idea, these 2's also will be Ideas
of some kind. And the same account applies to the units; for
the units in the first 2 generate the four in 4, so that all
the units come to be Ideas and an Idea will be composed of Ideas.
Clearly therefore those things also of which these happen to
be the Ideas will be composite, e.g. one might say that animals
are composed of animals, if there are Ideas of them.
"In
general, to differentiate the units in any way is an absurdity
and a fiction; and by a fiction I mean a forced statement made
to suit a hypothesis. For neither in quantity nor in quality
do we see unit differing from unit, and number must be either
equal or unequal-all number but especially that which consists
of abstract units-so that if one number is neither greater nor
less than another, it is equal to it; but things that are equal
and in no wise differentiated we take to be the same when we
are speaking of numbers. If not, not even the 2 in the 10-itself
will be undifferentiated, though they are equal; for what reason
will the man who alleges that they are not differentiated be
able to give?
"Again, if every unit + another unit makes
two, a unit from the 2-itself and one from the 3-itself will
make a 2. Now (a) this will consist of differentiated units;
and will it be prior to the 3 or posterior? It rather seems that
it must be prior; for one of the units is simultaneous with the
3 and the other is simultaneous with the 2. And we, for our part,
suppose that in general 1 and 1, whether the things are equal
or unequal, is 2, e.g. the good and the bad, or a man and a horse;
but those who hold these views say that not even two units are
2.
"If the number of the 3-itself is not greater than
that of the 2, this is surprising; and if it is greater, clearly
there is also a number in it equal to the 2, so that this is
not different from the 2-itself. But this is not possible, if
there is a first and a second number.
"Nor will the Ideas
be numbers. For in this particular point they are right who claim
that the units must be different, if there are to be Ideas; as
has been said before. For the Form is unique; but if the units
are not different, the 2's and the 3's also will not be different.
This is also the reason why they must say that when we count
thus-'1,2'-we do not proceed by adding to the given number; for
if we do, neither will the numbers be generated from the indefinite
dyad, nor can a number be an Idea; for then one Idea will be
in another, and all Forms will be parts of one Form. And so with
a view to their hypothesis their statements are right, but as
a whole they are wrong; for their view is very destructive, since
they will admit that this question itself affords some difficulty-whether,
when we count and say -1,2,3-we count by addition or by separate
portions. But we do both; and so it is absurd to reason back
from this problem to so great a difference of essence.
Part 8
"First of all it is well to determine what is the differentia
of a number-and of a unit, if it has a differentia. Units must
differ either in quantity or in quality; and neither of these
seems to be possible. But number qua number differs in quantity.
And if the units also did differ in quantity, number would differ
from number, though equal in number of units. Again, are the
first units greater or smaller, and do the later ones increase
or diminish? All these are irrational suppositions. But neither
can they differ in quality. For no attribute can attach to them;
for even to numbers quality is said to belong after quantity.
Again, quality could not come to them either from the 1 or the
dyad; for the former has no quality, and the latter gives quantity;
for this entity is what makes things to be many. If the facts
are really otherwise, they should state this quite at the beginning
and determine if possible, regarding the differentia of the unit,
why it must exist, and, failing this, what differentia they mean.
"Evidently then, if the Ideas are numbers, the units
cannot all be associable, nor can they be inassociable in either
of the two ways. But neither is the way in which some others
speak about numbers correct. These are those who do not think
there are Ideas, either without qualification or as identified
with certain numbers, but think the objects of mathematics exist
and the numbers are the first of existing things, and the 1-itself
is the starting-point of them. It is paradoxical that there should
be a 1 which is first of 1's, as they say, but not a 2 which
is first of 2's, nor a 3 of 3's; for the same reasoning applies
to all. If, then, the facts with regard to number are so, and
one supposes mathematical number alone to exist, the 1 is not
the starting-point (for this sort of 1 must differ from the-other
units; and if this is so, there must also be a 2 which is first
of 2's, and similarly with the other successive numbers). But
if the 1 is the starting-point, the truth about the numbers must
rather be what Plato used to say, and there must be a first 2
and 3 and numbers must not be associable with one another. But
if on the other hand one supposes this, many impossible results,
as we have said, follow. But either this or the other must be
the case, so that if neither is, number cannot exist separately.
"It is evident, also, from this that the third version
is the worst,-the view ideal and mathematical number is the same.
For two mistakes must then meet in the one opinion. (1) Mathematical
number cannot be of this sort, but the holder of this view has
to spin it out by making suppositions peculiar to himself. And
(2) he must also admit all the consequences that confront those
who speak of number in the sense of 'Forms'.
"The Pythagorean
version in one way affords fewer difficulties than those before
named, but in another way has others peculiar to itself. For
not thinking of number as capable of existing separately removes
many of the impossible consequences; but that bodies should be
composed of numbers, and that this should be mathematical number,
is impossible. For it is not true to speak of indivisible spatial
magnitudes; and however much there might be magnitudes of this
sort, units at least have not magnitude; and how can a magnitude
be composed of indivisibles? But arithmetical number, at least,
consists of units, while these thinkers identify number with
real things; at any rate they apply their propositions to bodies
as if they consisted of those numbers.
"If, then, it
is necessary, if number is a self-subsistent real thing, that
it should exist in one of these ways which have been mentioned,
and if it cannot exist in any of these, evidently number has
no such nature as those who make it separable set up for it.
"Again, does each unit come from the great and the small,
equalized, or one from the small, another from the great? (a)
If the latter, neither does each thing contain all the elements,
nor are the units without difference; for in one there is the
great and in another the small, which is contrary in its nature
to the great. Again, how is it with the units in the 3-itself?
One of them is an odd unit. But perhaps it is for this reason
that they give 1-itself the middle place in odd numbers. (b)
But if each of the two units consists of both the great and the
small, equalized, how will the 2 which is a single thing, consist
of the great and the small? Or how will it differ from the unit?
Again, the unit is prior to the 2; for when it is destroyed the
2 is destroyed. It must, then, be the Idea of an Idea since it
is prior to an Idea, and it must have come into being before
it. From what, then? Not from the indefinite dyad, for its function
was to double.
"Again, number must be either infinite
or finite; for these thinkers think of number as capable of existing
separately, so that it is not possible that neither of those
alternatives should be true. Clearly it cannot be infinite; for
infinite number is neither odd nor even, but the generation of
numbers is always the generation either of an odd or of an even
number; in one way, when 1 operates on an even number, an odd
number is produced; in another way, when 2 operates, the numbers
got from 1 by doubling are produced; in another way, when the
odd numbers operate, the other even numbers are produced. Again,
if every Idea is an Idea of something, and the numbers are Ideas,
infinite number itself will be an Idea of something, either of
some sensible thing or of something else. Yet this is not possible
in view of their thesis any more than it is reasonable in itself,
at least if they arrange the Ideas as they do.
"But if
number is finite, how far does it go? With regard to this not
only the fact but the reason should be stated. But if number
goes only up to 10 as some say, firstly the Forms will soon run
short; e.g. if 3 is man-himself, what number will be the horse-itself?
The series of the numbers which are the several things-themselves
goes up to 10. It must, then, be one of the numbers within these
limits; for it is these that are substances and Ideas. Yet they
will run short; for the various forms of animal will outnumber
them. At the same time it is clear that if in this way the 3
is man-himself, the other 3's are so also (for those in identical
numbers are similar), so that there will be an infinite number
of men; if each 3 is an Idea, each of the numbers will be man-himself,
and if not, they will at least be men. And if the smaller number
is part of the greater (being number of such a sort that the
units in the same number are associable), then if the 4-itself
is an Idea of something, e.g. of 'horse' or of 'white', man will
be a part of horse, if man is It is paradoxical also that there
should be an Idea of 10 but not of 11, nor of the succeeding
numbers. Again, there both are and come to be certain things
of which there are no Forms; why, then, are there not Forms of
them also? We infer that the Forms are not causes. Again, it
is paradoxical-if the number series up to 10 is more of a real
thing and a Form than 10 itself. There is no generation of the
former as one thing, and there is of the latter. But they try
to work on the assumption that the series of numbers up to 10
is a complete series. At least they generate the derivatives-e.g.
the void, proportion, the odd, and the others of this kind-within
the decade. For some things, e.g. movement and rest, good and
bad, they assign to the originative principles, and the others
to the numbers. This is why they identify the odd with 1; for
if the odd implied 3 how would 5 be odd? Again, spatial magnitudes
and all such things are explained without going beyond a definite
number; e.g. the first, the indivisible, line, then the 2 &c.;
these entities also extend only up to 10.
"Again, if
number can exist separately, one might ask which is prior- 1,
or 3 or 2? Inasmuch as the number is composite, 1 is prior, but
inasmuch as the universal and the form is prior, the number is
prior; for each of the units is part of the number as its matter,
and the number acts as form. And in a sense the right angle is
prior to the acute, because it is determinate and in virtue of
its definition; but in a sense the acute is prior, because it
is a part and the right angle is divided into acute angles. As
matter, then, the acute angle and the element and the unit are
prior, but in respect of the form and of the substance as expressed
in the definition, the right angle, and the whole consisting
of the matter and the form, are prior; for the concrete thing
is nearer to the form and to what is expressed in the definition,
though in generation it is later. How then is 1 the starting-point?
Because it is not divisiable, they say; but both the universal,
and the particular or the element, are indivisible. But they
are starting-points in different ways, one in definition and
the other in time. In which way, then, is 1 the starting-point?
As has been said, the right angle is thought to be prior to the
acute, and the acute to the right, and each is one. Accordingly
they make 1 the starting-point in both ways. But this is impossible.
For the universal is one as form or substance, while the element
is one as a part or as matter. For each of the two is in a sense
one-in truth each of the two units exists potentially (at least
if the number is a unity and not like a heap, i.e. if different
numbers consist of differentiated units, as they say), but not
in complete reality; and the cause of the error they fell into
is that they were conducting their inquiry at the same time from
the standpoint of mathematics and from that of universal definitions,
so that (1) from the former standpoint they treated unity, their
first principle, as a point; for the unit is a point without
position. They put things together out of the smallest parts,
as some others also have done. Therefore the unit becomes the
matter of numbers and at the same time prior to 2; and again
posterior, 2 being treated as a whole, a unity, and a form. But
(2) because they were seeking the universal they treated the
unity which can be predicated of a number, as in this sense also
a part of the number. But these characteristics cannot belong
at the same time to the same thing.
"If the 1-itself
must be unitary (for it differs in nothing from other 1's except
that it is the starting-point), and the 2 is divisible but the
unit is not, the unit must be liker the 1-itself than the 2 is.
But if the unit is liker it, it must be liker to the unit than
to the 2; therefore each of the units in 2 must be prior to the
2. But they deny this; at least they generate the 2 first. Again,
if the 2-itself is a unity and the 3-itself is one also, both
form a 2. From what, then, is this 2 produced?
Part 9
"Since there is not contact in numbers, but succession,
viz. between the units between which there is nothing, e.g. between
those in 2 or in 3 one might ask whether these succeed the 1-itself
or not, and whether, of the terms that succeed it, 2 or either
of the units in 2 is prior.
"Similar difficulties occur
with regard to the classes of things posterior to number,-the
line, the plane, and the solid. For some construct these out
of the species of the 'great and small'; e.g. lines from the
'long and short', planes from the 'broad and narrow', masses
from the 'deep and shallow'; which are species of the 'great
and small'. And the originative principle of such things which
answers to the 1 different thinkers describe in different ways,
And in these also the impossibilities, the fictions, and the
contradictions of all probability are seen to be innumerable.
For (i) geometrical classes are severed from one another, unless
the principles of these are implied in one another in such a
way that the 'broad and narrow' is also 'long and short' (but
if this is so, the plane will be line and the solid a plane;
again, how will angles and figures and such things be explained?).
And (ii) the same happens as in regard to number; for 'long and
short', &c., are attributes of magnitude, but magnitude does
not consist of these, any more than the line consists of 'straight
and curved', or solids of 'smooth and rough'.
"(All these
views share a difficulty which occurs with regard to species-of-a-genus,
when one posits the universals, viz. whether it is animal-itself
or something other than animal-itself that is in the particular
animal. True, if the universal is not separable from sensible
things, this will present no difficulty; but if the 1 and the
numbers are separable, as those who express these views say,
it is not easy to solve the difficulty, if one may apply the
words 'not easy' to the impossible. For when we apprehend the
unity in 2, or in general in a number, do we apprehend a thing-itself
or something else?).
"Some, then, generate spatial magnitudes
from matter of this sort, others from the point -and the point
is thought by them to be not 1 but something like 1-and from
other matter like plurality, but not identical with it; about
which principles none the less the same difficulties occur. For
if the matter is one, line and plane-and soli will be the same;
for from the same elements will come one and the same thing.
But if the matters are more than one, and there is one for the
line and a second for the plane and another for the solid, they
either are implied in one another or not, so that the same results
will follow even so; for either the plane will not contain a
line or it will he a line.
"Again, how number can consist
of the one and plurality, they make no attempt to explain; but
however they express themselves, the same objections arise as
confront those who construct number out of the one and the indefinite
dyad. For the one view generates number from the universally
predicated plurality, and not from a particular plurality; and
the other generates it from a particular plurality, but the first;
for 2 is said to be a 'first plurality'. Therefore there is practically
no difference, but the same difficulties will follow,-is it intermixture
or position or blending or generation? and so on. Above all one
might press the question 'if each unit is one, what does it come
from?' Certainly each is not the one-itself. It must, then, come
from the one itself and plurality, or a part of plurality. To
say that the unit is a plurality is impossible, for it is indivisible;
and to generate it from a part of plurality involves many other
objections; for (a) each of the parts must be indivisible (or
it will be a plurality and the unit will be divisible) and the
elements will not be the one and plurality; for the single units
do not come from plurality and the one. Again, (,the holder of
this view does nothing but presuppose another number; for his
plurality of indivisibles is a number. Again, we must inquire,
in view of this theory also, whether the number is infinite or
finite. For there was at first, as it seems, a plurality that
was itself finite, from which and from the one comes the finite
number of units. And there is another plurality that is plurality-itself
and infinite plurality; which sort of plurality, then, is the
element which co-operates with the one? One might inquire similarly
about the point, i.e. the element out of which they make spatial
magnitudes. For surely this is not the one and only point; at
any rate, then, let them say out of what each of the points is
formed. Certainly not of some distance + the point-itself. Nor
again can there be indivisible parts of a distance, as the elements
out of which the units are said to be made are indivisible parts
of plurality; for number consists of indivisibles, but spatial
magnitudes do not.
"All these objections, then, and others
of the sort make it evident that number and spatial magnitudes
cannot exist apart from things. Again, the discord about numbers
between the various versions is a sign that it is the incorrectness
of the alleged facts themselves that brings confusion into the
theories. For those who make the objects of mathematics alone
exist apart from sensible things, seeing the difficulty about
the Forms and their fictitiousness, abandoned ideal number and
posited mathematical. But those who wished to make the Forms
at the same time also numbers, but did not see, if one assumed
these principles, how mathematical number was to exist apart
from ideal, made ideal and mathematical number the same-in words,
since in fact mathematical number has been destroyed; for they
state hypotheses peculiar to themselves and not those of mathematics.
And he who first supposed that the Forms exist and that the Forms
are numbers and that the objects of mathematics exist, naturally
separated the two. Therefore it turns out that all of them are
right in some respect, but on the whole not right. And they themselves
confirm this, for their statements do not agree but conflict.
The cause is that their hypotheses and their principles are false.
And it is hard to make a good case out of bad materials, according
to Epicharmus: 'as soon as 'tis said, 'tis seen to be wrong.'
"But regarding numbers the questions we have raised and
the conclusions we have reached are sufficient (for while he
who is already convinced might be further convinced by a longer
discussion, one not yet convinced would not come any nearer to
conviction); regarding the first principles and the first causes
and elements, the views expressed by those who discuss only sensible
substance have been partly stated in our works on nature, and
partly do not belong to the present inquiry; but the views of
those who assert that there are other substances besides the
sensible must be considered next after those we have been mentioning.
Since, then, some say that the Ideas and the numbers are such
substances, and that the elements of these are elements and principles
of real things, we must inquire regarding these what they say
and in what sense they say it.
"Those who posit numbers
only, and these mathematical, must be considered later; but as
regards those who believe in the Ideas one might survey at the
same time their way of thinking and the difficulty into which
they fall. For they at the same time make the Ideas universal
and again treat them as separable and as individuals. That this
is not possible has been argued before. The reason why those
who described their substances as universal combined these two
characteristics in one thing, is that they did not make substances
identical with sensible things. They thought that the particulars
in the sensible world were a state of flux and none of them remained,
but that the universal was apart from these and something different.
And Socrates gave the impulse to this theory, as we said in our
earlier discussion, by reason of his definitions, but he did
not separate universals from individuals; and in this he thought
rightly, in not separating them. This is plain from the results;
for without the universal it is not possible to get knowledge,
but the separation is the cause of the objections that arise
with regard to the Ideas. His successors, however, treating it
as necessary, if there are to be any substances besides the sensible
and transient substances, that they must be separable, had no
others, but gave separate existence to these universally predicated
substances, so that it followed that universals and individuals
were almost the same sort of thing. This in itself, then, would
be one difficulty in the view we have mentioned.
Part 10
"Let us now mention a point which presents a certain
difficulty both to those who believe in the Ideas and to those
who do not, and which was stated before, at the beginning, among
the problems. If we do not suppose substances to be separate,
and in the way in which individual things are said to be separate,
we shall destroy substance in the sense in which we understand
'substance'; but if we conceive substances to be separable, how
are we to conceive their elements and their principles?
"If
they are individual and not universal, (a) real things will be
just of the same number as the elements, and (b) the elements
will not be knowable. For (a) let the syllables in speech be
substances, and their elements elements of substances; then there
must be only one 'ba' and one of each of the syllables, since
they are not universal and the same in form but each is one in
number and a 'this' and not a kind possessed of a common name
(and again they suppose that the 'just what a thing is' is in
each case one). And if the syllables are unique, so too are the
parts of which they consist; there will not, then, be more a's
than one, nor more than one of any of the other elements, on
the same principle on which an identical syllable cannot exist
in the plural number. But if this is so, there will not be other
things existing besides the elements, but only the elements.
"(b) Again, the elements will not be even knowable; for
they are not universal, and knowledge is of universals. This
is clear from demonstrations and from definitions; for we do
not conclude that this triangle has its angles equal to two right
angles, unless every triangle has its angles equal to two right
angles, nor that this man is an animal, unless every man is an
animal.
"But if the principles are universal, either
the substances composed of them are also universal, or non-substance
will be prior to substance; for the universal is not a substance,
but the element or principle is universal, and the element or
principle is prior to the things of which it is the principle
or element.
"All these difficulties follow naturally,
when they make the Ideas out of elements and at the same time
claim that apart from the substances which have the same form
there are Ideas, a single separate entity. But if, e.g. in the
case of the elements of speech, the a's and the b's may quite
well be many and there need be no a-itself and b-itself besides
the many, there may be, so far as this goes, an infinite number
of similar syllables. The statement that an knowledge is universal,
so that the principles of things must also be universal and not
separate substances, presents indeed, of all the points we have
mentioned, the greatest difficulty, but yet the statement is
in a sense true, although in a sense it is not. For knowledge,
like the verb 'to know', means two things, of which one is potential
and one actual. The potency, being, as matter, universal and
indefinite, deals with the universal and indefinite; but the
actuality, being definite, deals with a definite object, being
a 'this', it deals with a 'this'. But per accidents sight sees
universal colour, because this individual colour which it sees
is colour; and this individual a which the grammarian investigates
is an a. For if the principles must be universal, what is derived
from them must also be universal, as in demonstrations; and if
this is so, there will be nothing capable of separate existence-i.e.
no substance. But evidently in a sense knowledge is universal,
and in a sense it is not.
END
Back to list